Ευρωπαϊκό Δικαστήριο των Δικαιωμάτων του Ανθρώπου, Απόφαση της 18ης
Μαρτίου 2011 στην υπόθεση LAUTSI και λοιπών κατά Ιταλίας (αριθμός
αιτήσεως 30814/06)
Η Μείζων Σύνθεση του Ευρωπαϊκού
Δικαστηρίου Δικαιωμάτων του Ανθρώπου δημοσίευσε την Παρασκευή 18.3.2011,
την ληφθείσα κατά πλειοψηφία - με δέκα πέντε ψήφους υπέρ (με
συγκλίνουσα γνώμη και του Έλληνα δικαστή) και δύο......
ψήφους κατά - απόφασή
της, κατά την οποία η παρουσία του σταυρού στις σχολικές αίθουσες της
Ιταλίας δεν συνιστά παραβίαση του δικαιώματος των γονέων να μορφώνουν τα
τέκνα τους με βάση τις θρησκευτικές και φιλοσοφικές τους πεποιθήσεις
κατά το άρθρο 2 του 1ου Πρωτοκόλλου της Ευρωπαΐκής Σύμβασεως των
ΔΙκαιωμάτων του Ανθρώπου (ΕΣΔΑ). Στην σχετική δίκη είχε παρέμβει με
επιχειρήματα υπέρ της παρουσίας του Τιμίου Σταυρού στις σχολικές
αίθουσες, μεταξύ άλλων κρατών, και η Ελληνική Κυβέρνηση.
==================
GRAND
CHAMBER
CASE OF LAUTSI AND OTHERS
v. ITALY
(Application no. 30814/06)
JUDGMENT
STRASBOURG
18
March 2011
This judgment is final but may be subject to editorial
revision.
In the case of Lautsi
and Others v. Italy,
The European Court of Human Rights, sitting as
a Grand Chamber composed of:
Jean-Paul Costa, President,
Christos Rozakis,
Nicolas Bratza,
Peer Lorenzen,
Josep Casadevall,
Giovanni Bonello,
Christos Rozakis,
Nicolas Bratza,
Peer Lorenzen,
Josep Casadevall,
Giovanni Bonello,
Nina Vajić,
Rait Maruste,
Anatoly Kovler,
Sverre Erik Jebens,
Päivi Hirvelä,
Giorgio Malinverni,
George Nicolaou,
Ann Power,
Zdravka Kalaydjieva,
Rait Maruste,
Anatoly Kovler,
Sverre Erik Jebens,
Päivi Hirvelä,
Giorgio Malinverni,
George Nicolaou,
Ann Power,
Zdravka Kalaydjieva,
Mihai Poalelungi,
Guido Raimondi, judges,
and Erik Fribergh, Registrar,
Guido Raimondi, judges,
and Erik Fribergh, Registrar,
Having deliberated in private on 30 June 2010
and on 16 February 2011,
Delivers the following judgment, which was
adopted on the last‑mentioned date:
PROCEDURE
1. The case originated in an
application (no. 30814/06) against the Italian Republic
lodged with the Court under Article 34 of the Convention for the Protection of
Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (“the Convention”) by an Italian
national, Ms Soile Lautsi (“the first applicant”) on 27 July 2006. In her
application she stated that she was acting in her own name and on behalf of her
children Dataico and Sami Albertin, then minors. The latter, who have
subsequently come of age, confirmed that they wished to remain applicants (“the
second and third applicants”).
2. The applicants were
represented by Mr N. Paoletti, a lawyer practising in Rome. The Italian Government (“the Government”)
were represented by their Agent, Ms E. Spatafora, and their deputy co-Agents,
Mr N. Lettieri and Ms P. Accardo.
3. The application was
allocated to the Court's Second Section (Rule 52 § 1 of the Rules of
Court). On 1 July 2008 a Chamber of that Section, composed of the following
judges: Françoise Tulkens, Antonella Mularoni, Vladimiro Zagrebelsky, Danutė
Jočienė, Dragoljub Popović, András Sajó and Işıl Karakaş, decided to give
notice of the application to the Government; applying the provisions of Article
29 § 3 of the Convention, it also decided to rule on the admissibility and
merits of the application at the same time.
4. On 3 November 2009 a Chamber
of the same Section, composed of the following judges: Françoise Tulkens,
Ireneu Cabral Barreto, Vladimiro Zagrebelsky, Danutė Jočienė, Dragoljub
Popović, András Sajó and Işıl Karakaş, declared the application admissible and
held unanimously that there had been a violation of Article 2 of Protocol No.
1, taken together with Article 9 of the Convention, and that it was not
necessary to examine the complaint under Article 14 of the Convention.
5. On 28 January 2010 the
Government asked for the case to be referred to the Grand Chamber by virtue of
Article 43 of the Convention and Rule 73. On 1 March 2010 a panel of the Grand
Chamber granted that request.
6. The composition of the
Grand Chamber was determined according to the provisions of Article 26 §§ 4 and
5 of the Convention and Rule 24.
7. The applicants and the
Government each filed further written observations on the merits.
8. Leave to intervene in the
written procedure (Article 36 § 2 of the Convention and Rule 44 § 2) was given
to thirty-three members of the European Parliament acting collectively, the
non-governmental organisation Greek Helsinki Monitor, which had previously
intervened before the Chamber, the non-governmental organisation Associazione nazionale del libero Pensiero,
the non-governmental organisation European Centre for Law and Justice, the
non-governmental organisation Eurojuris, the non-governmental organisations
International Committee of Jurists, Interights and Human Rights Watch, acting
collectively, the non-governmental organisations Zentralkomitee der deutschen Katholiken, Semaines sociales de France and Associazioni
cristiane lavoratori italiani, acting collectively, and the Governments of
Armenia, Bulgaria, Cyprus, the Russian Federation, Greece, Lithuania, Malta,
Monaco, Romania and the Republic of San Marino.
The Governments of Armenia, Bulgaria, Cyprus,
the Russian Federation, Greece, Lithuania,
Malta, and the Republic of San Marino were also given leave to
intervene collectively in the oral procedure.
9. A hearing took place in
public in the Human Rights Building,
Strasbourg, on 30
June 2010 (Rule 59 § 3).
There appeared before the Court:
(a) for the respondent
Government
Mr Nicola Lettieri, co-Agent,
Mr Giuseppe Albenzio, Adviser;
Mr Nicola Lettieri, co-Agent,
Mr Giuseppe Albenzio, Adviser;
(b) for the applicants
Mr Nicolò Paoletti, Counsel,
Ms Natalia Paoletti,
Ms Claudia Sartori, Advisers;
Mr Nicolò Paoletti, Counsel,
Ms Natalia Paoletti,
Ms Claudia Sartori, Advisers;
(c) for the
Governments of Armenia, Bulgaria, Cyprus,
the Russian Federation, Greece, Lithuania,
Malta, and the Republic of San Marino, third-party interveners:
Mr Joseph
Weiler, Professor of Law, New York University, Counsel,
Mr Stepan Kartashyan, Deputy Permanent Representative
of Armenia to the Council of Europe,
Mr Andrey Tehov, Ambassador, Permanent Representative
of Bulgaria to the Council of Europe,
Mr Yannis Michilides, Deputy Permanent Representative of Cyprus
to the Council of Europe,
Ms Vasileia Pelekou, Deputy Permanent Representative of
Greece to the Council of Europe,
Mr Darius Šimaitis, Deputy Permanent Representative of
Lithuania to the Council of Europe,
Mr Joseph Licari, Ambassador, Permanent Representative
of Malta to the Council of Europe,
Mr Georgy Matyushkin, Government Agent of the
Russian Federation,
Mr Guido Bellatti Ceccioli, co-Agent of the Government
of the Republic of San Marino, Advisers.
Mr Stepan Kartashyan, Deputy Permanent Representative
of Armenia to the Council of Europe,
Mr Andrey Tehov, Ambassador, Permanent Representative
of Bulgaria to the Council of Europe,
Mr Yannis Michilides, Deputy Permanent Representative of Cyprus
to the Council of Europe,
Ms Vasileia Pelekou, Deputy Permanent Representative of
Greece to the Council of Europe,
Mr Darius Šimaitis, Deputy Permanent Representative of
Lithuania to the Council of Europe,
Mr Joseph Licari, Ambassador, Permanent Representative
of Malta to the Council of Europe,
Mr Georgy Matyushkin, Government Agent of the
Russian Federation,
Mr Guido Bellatti Ceccioli, co-Agent of the Government
of the Republic of San Marino, Advisers.
The Court heard addresses by Mr Nicolò
Paoletti, Ms Natalia Paoletti, Mr Lettieri, Mr Albenzio and Mr Weiler.
THE FACTS
I. THE
CIRCUMSTANCES OF THE CASE
10. The first applicant and
her two sons, Dataico and Sami Albertin, also applicants, were born in 1957,
1988 and 1990 respectively. They are resident in Italy. In the school year 2001-2002
Dataico and Sami attended the Istituto comprensivo statale Vittorino da Feltre,
a State school in Abano Terme. A crucifix was fixed to the wall in each of the
school's classrooms.
11. On 22 April 2002, during
a meeting of the school's governors, the first applicant's husband raised the
question of the presence of religious symbols in the classrooms, particularly
mentioning crucifixes, and asked whether they ought to be removed. On 27 May
2002, by ten votes to two with one abstention, the school's governors decided
to keep religious symbols in classrooms.
12. On 23 July 2002 the first
applicant contested that decision in
the Veneto Administrative Court, complaining of an infringement of the principle
of secularism, relying in that connection on Articles 3 (principle of equality)
and 19 (religious freedom) of the Italian Constitution and Article 9 of
the Convention, and on the principle of the impartiality of public
administrative authorities (Article 97 of the Constitution).
13. On 3 October 2002 the
Minister of Education, Universities and Research adopted Directive
no. 2666, instructing the competent services of his Ministry to take the
necessary measures to see to it that school governors ensured the presence of
crucifixes in classrooms (see paragraph 24 below).
On 30 October 2003 the Minister joined the
proceedings brought by the first applicant. He argued that her application was
ill-founded since the presence of crucifixes in the classrooms of publicly run
schools was based on Article 118 of royal decree no. 965 of 30 April 1924
(internal regulations of middle schools) and Article 119 of royal decree no.
1297 of 26 April 1928 (approval of the general regulations governing primary
education; see paragraph 19 below).
14. By a decision of 14
January 2004 the Administrative Court referred to the Constitutional Court the
question of the constitutionality, with regard to the principle of the secular
character of the State and Articles 2, 3, 7, 8, 19 and 20 of the Constitution,
of Articles 159 and 190 of legislative decree no. 297 of 16 April 1994
(approving the single text bringing together the legislative provisions in
force regarding education and schools), in their “specifications” resulting
from Articles 118 and 119 of the above-mentioned royal decrees, and of Article
676 of the same legislative decree.
Articles 159 and 190 make municipalities
responsible for purchasing and supplying the furniture of primary and middle
schools. Article 119 of the 1928 decree specifies that each classroom must have
a crucifix and Article 118 of the 1924 decree that each classroom must have a portrait
of the king and a crucifix. Article 676 of legislative decree no. 297 stipulates
that provisions not included in the single text remain in force, “with the
exception of provisions contrary to or incompatible with the single text, which
are repealed”.
By a decision of 15 December 2004 (no. 389),
the Constitutional Court declared the question as to constitutionality
manifestly inadmissible, on the ground that it was in reality directed towards
texts which, not having the status of law, but only that of regulations (the
above-mentioned Articles 118 and 119), could not form the subject of a review
of constitutionality.
15. On 17 March 2005 the Administrative Court
dismissed the application. After ruling that Article 118 of the royal decree of
30 April 1924 and Article 119 of the royal decree of 26 April 1928 were
still in force and emphasising that “the principle of the secular nature of the
State [was] now part of the legal heritage of Europe and the western
democracies”, it held that the presence of crucifixes in State-school
classrooms, regard being had to the meaning it should be understood to convey,
did not offend against that principle. It took the view, in particular, that
although the crucifix was undeniably a religious symbol, it was a symbol of
Christianity in general rather than of Catholicism alone, so that it served as
a point of reference for other creeds. It went on to say that the crucifix was
a historical and cultural symbol, possessing on that account an “identity-linked
value” for the Italian people, in that it “represent[ed] in a way the historical
and cultural development characteristic of [Italy] and in general of the whole
of Europe, and [was] a good synthesis of that development”. The Administrative Court
further held that the crucifix should also be considered a symbol of a value
system underpinning the Italian Constitution. It gave the following reasons:
“... 11.1. At this stage, the Court
must observe, although it is aware that it is setting out along a rough and in
places slippery path, that Christianity, and its older brother Judaism – at
least since Moses and certainly in the Talmudic interpretation – have placed
tolerance towards others and protection of human dignity at the centre of their
faith.
Singularly, Christianity – for example through
the well-known and often misunderstood “Render unto Caesar the things which are
Caesar's, and unto ...” – through its strong emphasis placed on love for one's
neighbour, and even more through the explicit predominance given to charity
over faith itself, contains in substance those ideas of tolerance, equality and
liberty which form the basis of the modern secular State, and of the Italian
State in particular.
11.2 Looking beyond appearances
makes it possible to discern a thread linking the Christian revolution of two
thousand years ago to the affirmation in Europe of the right to liberty of the
person and to the key elements in the Enlightenment (even though that movement,
historically speaking, strongly opposed religion), namely the liberty and
freedom of every person, the declaration of the rights of man, and ultimately
the modern secular State. All the historic phenomena mentioned are based to a
significant extent – though certainly not exclusively – on the Christian
conception of the world. It has been observed – judiciously – that the rallying
call “liberty, equality, fraternity” can easily be endorsed by a Christian,
albeit with a clear emphasis on the third word.
In conclusion, it does not seem to be going
too far to assert that, through the various twists and turns of European
history, the secular nature of the modern State has been achieved at a high
price, and was prompted in part, though of course not exclusively so, by a more
or less conscious reference to the founding values of Christianity. That
explains why in Europe and in Italy
many jurists belonging to the Christian faith have featured among the strongest
supporters of the secular State. ...
11.5 The link between Christianity
and liberty implies a logical historical coherence which is not immediately obvious
– like a river in a karst landscape which has only recently been explored,
precisely because for most of its course it flows underground – partly because
in the constantly changing relations between the States and Churches of Europe
it is much easier to see the numerous attempts by the Churches to meddle in
matters of State, and vice versa, just like the frequent occasions on which
Christian ideals have been abandoned, though officially proclaimed, in the
quest for power, or on which governments and religious authorities have clashed,
sometimes violently.
11.6 Moreover, with the benefit of
hindsight, it is easy to identify in the constant central core of Christian
faith, despite the inquisition, despite anti-Semitism and despite the crusades,
the principles of human dignity, tolerance and freedom, including religious
freedom, and therefore, in the last analysis, the foundations of the secular
State.
11.7 By studying history carefully,
from a suitable distance, not from up close, we can clearly perceive an
affinity between (but not the identity of) the “hard core” of Christianity,
which, placing charity above everything else, including faith, emphasises the
acceptance of difference, and the “hard core” of the republican Constitution,
which, in a spirit of solidarity, attaches value to the freedom of all, and
therefore constitutes the legal guarantee of respect for others. The harmony
remains, even though around those cores – both centred on human dignity – there
have been numerous accretions of extraneous elements with the passage of time,
some of them so thick as to obscure the core, particularly the core of
Christianity. ...
11.9 It can therefore be contended
that in the present-day social reality the crucifix should be regarded not only
as a symbol of a historical and cultural development, and therefore of the
identity of our people, but also as a symbol of a value system: liberty,
equality, human dignity and religious toleration, and accordingly also of the
secular nature of the State – principles which underpin our Constitution.
In other words, the constitutional principles
of freedom have many roots, which undeniably include Christianity, in its very
essence. It would therefore be something of a paradox to exclude a Christian
sign from a public institution in the name of secularism, one of whose distant
sources is precisely the Christian religion.
12.1 This court is admittedly not
unaware of the fact that, in the past, other values have been attributed to the
symbol of the crucifix, such as, at the time of the Albertine Statute, the sign
of Catholicism understood as the State religion, and therefore used to
Christianise and consolidate power and authority.
The court is well aware, moreover, that it is
still possible today to give various interpretations of the sign of the cross,
and above all a strictly religious meaning referring to Christianity in general
and Catholicism in particular. It is also aware that some pupils attending
State schools might freely and legitimately attribute to the cross values which
are different again, such as the sign of an unacceptable preference for one
religion in relation to others, or an infringement of individual freedom and
accordingly of the secular nature of the State, or at the extreme limit a
reference to temporal political control over a State religion, or the
inquisition, or even a free catechism voucher tacitly distributed even to
non-believers in an inappropriate place, or subliminal propaganda in favour of
Christian creeds. Although all those points of view are respectable, they are
ultimately irrelevant in the present case. ...
12.6 It must be emphasised that the
symbol of the crucifix, thus understood, now possesses, through its references
to the values of tolerance, a particular scope in consideration of the fact
that at present Italian State schools are attended by numerous pupils from
outside the European Union, to whom it is relatively important to transmit the
principles of openness to diversity and the refusal of any form of
fundamentalism – whether religious or secular – which permeate our system. Our
era is marked by the ferment resulting from the meeting of different cultures
with our own, and to prevent that meeting from turning into a collision it is
indispensable to reaffirm our identity, even symbolically, especially as it is
characterised precisely by the values of respect for the dignity of each human
being and of universal solidarity. ...
13.2 In fact, religious symbols in
general imply a logical exclusion mechanism, as the point of departure of any
religious faith is precisely the belief in a superior entity, which is why its
adherents, the faithful, see themselves by definition and by conviction as part
of the truth. Consequently, and inevitably, the attitude of the believer, faced
with someone who does not believe, and who is therefore implicitly opposed to
the supreme being, is an attitude of exclusion. ...
13.3 The logical mechanism of
exclusion of the unbeliever is inherent in any religious conviction, even if
those concerned are not aware of it, the sole exception being Christianity –
where it is properly understood, which of course has not always been and still
is not always the case, not even thanks to those who call themselves Christian.
In Christianity even the faith in an omniscient god is secondary in relation to
charity, meaning respect for one's fellow human beings. It follows that the
rejection of a non-Christian by a Christian implies a radical negation of
Christianity itself, a substantive abjuration; but that is not true of other
religious faiths, for which such an attitude amounts at most to the
infringement of an important precept.
13.4 The cross, as the symbol of
Christianity, can therefore not exclude anyone without denying itself; it even
constitutes in a sense the universal sign of the acceptance of and respect for
every human being as such, irrespective of any belief, religious or other,
which he or she may hold. ...
14.1 It is hardly necessary to add
that the sign of the cross in a classroom, when correctly understood, is not
concerned with the freely held convictions of anyone, excludes no one and of
course does not impose or prescribe anything, but merely implies, in the heart
of the aims set for education and teaching in a publicly run school, a
reflection – necessarily guided by the teaching staff – on Italian history and
the common values of our society legally retranscribed in the Constitution,
among which the secular nature of the State has pride of place. ...”
16. The first applicant appealed
to the Consiglio di Stato (Supreme
Administrative Court), which confirmed that the presence of crucifixes in State-school
classrooms had its legal basis in Article 118 of the royal decree of 30 April
1924 and Article 119 of the royal decree of 26 April 1928 and, regard being had
to the meaning that should be attached to it, was compatible with the principle
of secularism. On that point it found in particular that in Italy the crucifix
symbolised the religious origin of values (tolerance, mutual respect,
valorisation of the person, affirmation of one's rights, consideration for one's
freedom, the autonomy of one's moral conscience vis-à-vis authority, human
solidarity and the refusal of any form of discrimination) which characterised
Italian civilisation. In that sense, when displayed in classrooms, the crucifix
could fulfil – even in a “secular” perspective distinct from the religious
perspective to which it specifically referred – a highly educational symbolic
function, irrespective of the religion professed by the pupils. The Consiglio di Stato held that the
crucifix had to be seen as a symbol capable of reflecting the remarkable
sources of the above-mentioned values, the values which defined secularism in
the State's present legal order.
In its judgment (no. 556) dated 13 April 2006
the Consiglio di Stato gave the
following reasoning:
“... the Constitutional Court has accepted on
a number of occasions that secularism is a supreme principle of our
constitutional order, capable of resolving certain questions of constitutional legitimacy
(among numerous judgments, see those which concern the provisions relating to
the compulsory nature of religious teaching in school or the jurisdiction of
the courts over cases concerning the validity of marriages contracted according
to canon law and recorded in the registers of marriages).
This is a principle which is not proclaimed in
express terms in our Constitution, a principle which is rich with ideological
resonances and has a history full of controversy, but one nevertheless which
has a legal importance that can be deduced from the fundamental norms of our
system. In reality the Court derives this principle specifically from Articles
2, 3, 7, 8, 19 and 20 of the Constitution.
The principle uses a linguistic symbol
(“secularism”) which indicates in abridged form certain significant aspects of
the above-mentioned provisions, the content of which established the operating conditions
under which this symbol should be understood and function. If these specific operating
conditions had not been established, the principle of “secularism” would remain
confined to ideological conflicts and could be used only with difficulty in a
legal framework.
In that framework, the operating conditions
are of course determined by reference to the cultural traditions and the
customs of each people, in so far as these traditions and customs are reflected
in the legal order, and this differs from one nation to another. ...
In the context of this court and the problem
placed before it, namely the legitimacy of displaying the crucifix in
classrooms, on the part of the competent authorities acting pursuant to the
regulations, what has to be done in practice is the simpler task of verifying
whether that requirement does or does not infringe the content of the
fundamental norms of our constitutional order, that give form and substance to
the principle of “secularism” which now characterises the Italian State and to
which the Constitutional Court has referred on a number of occasions.
Quite clearly, the crucifix is in itself a
symbol that may have various meanings and serve various purposes, above all for
the place in which it has been displayed.
In a place of worship the crucifix is properly
and exclusively a “religious symbol”, since it is intended to foster respectful
adherence to the founder of the Christian religion.
In a non-religious context like a school, used
for the education of young people, the crucifix may still convey the
above-mentioned values to believers, but for them and for non-believers its
display is justified and possesses a non-discriminatory meaning from the
religious point of view if it is capable of representing and evoking
synthetically and in an immediately perceptible and foreseeable manner (like
any symbol) values which are important for civil society, in particular the
values which underpin and inspire our constitutional order, the foundation of
our civil life. In that sense the crucifix can perform – even in a “secular”
perspective distinct from the religious perspective specific to it – a highly
educational symbolic function, irrespective of the religion professed by the
pupils.
Now it is obvious that in Italy the crucifix
is capable of expressing, symbolically of course, but appropriately, the
religious origin of those values – tolerance, mutual respect, valorisation of
the person, affirmation of one's rights, consideration for one's freedom, the
autonomy of one's moral conscience vis-à-vis authority, human solidarity and
the refusal of any form of discrimination – which characterise Italian
civilisation.
Those values, which have pervaded traditions,
a way of life, the culture of the Italian people, form the basis for and spring
from the fundamental norms of our founding charter – contained in the
“Fundamental Principles” and the first part – and especially from those which
the Constitutional Court referred to and which delimit the form of secularism
appropriate to the Italian State.
The reference, via the crucifix, to the
religious origin of these values and their full and complete correspondence with
Christian teachings accordingly makes plain the transcendent sources of the
values concerned, without calling into question, rather indeed confirming the autonomy
of the temporal power vis-à-vis the spiritual power (but not their opposition,
implicit in an ideological interpretation of secularism which has no equivalent
in the Constitution), and without taking anything away from their particular
“secular” nature, adapted to the cultural context specific to the fundamental
order of the Italian State and manifested by it. Those values are therefore experienced
in civil society autonomously (and not contradictorily) in relation to
religious society, so that they may be endorsed “secularly” by all,
irrespective of adhesion to the creed which inspired and defended them.
As with any symbol, one can impose on or
attribute to the crucifix various contrasting meanings; one can even deny its
symbolic value and make it a simple trinket having artistic value at the most.
However, a crucifix displayed in a classroom cannot be considered a trinket, a
decorative feature, nor as an adjunct to worship. Rather, it should be seen as a
symbol capable of reflecting the remarkable sources of the civil values referred
to above, values which define secularism in the State's present legal order. ...”
II. DEVELOPMENT
OF THE RELEVANT DOMESTIC LAW AND PRACTICE
17. The obligation to hang
crucifixes in primary school classrooms was laid down in Article 140 of royal
decree no. 4336 of 15 September 1860 of the Kingdom of
Piedmont-Sardinia, promulgated in accordance with Law no. 3725 of 13 November
1859, which provided: “each school must without fail be equipped with ... a crucifix”
(Article 140).
In 1861, the year which saw the birth of the Italian State,
the 1848 Statute of the Kingdom of Piedmont-Sardinia became the Constitution of
the Kingdom of Italy; it provided in particular: “the Roman
Catholic Apostolic religion shall be the only religion of the State [and] other
existing creeds shall be tolerated in conformity with the law”.
18. The capture of Rome by
the Italian army on 20 September 1870, following which the city was annexed and
proclaimed capital of the new Kingdom of Italy, caused a crisis in relations
between the State and the Catholic Church. By Law no. 214 of 13 May 1871
the Italian State unilaterally regulated relations
with the Church, granting the Pope a number of privileges for the orderly
conduct of religious activity. According to the applicants, the display of
crucifixes in schools fell little by little into disuse.
19. During the fascist period
the State took a series of measures aimed at ensuring compliance with the
obligation to display the crucifix in classrooms.
For instance, on 22 November 1922 the Ministry
of Education sent out a circular (no. 68) with the following wording: “... in
the last few years in many of the Kingdom's primary schools the image of Christ
and the portrait of the King have been removed. That is a manifest and
intolerable breach of the regulations and especially an attack on the dominant
religion of the State and the unity of the Nation. We therefore order all
municipal administrative authorities in the Kingdom to restore, to those
schools which lack them, the two sacred symbols of the faith and the
consciousness of nationhood.”
On 30 April 1924 royal decree no. 965 of
30 April 1924 was adopted. This decree laid down the internal regulations governing
middle schools (ordinamento interno delle
giunte e dei regi istituti di istruzione media). Article 118 provided:
“Each school must have the national flag and
each classroom must have a crucifix and a portrait of the King”.
Article 119 of royal decree no. 1297 of
26 April 1928, approving the general regulations governing the provision of primary
education (approvazione del regolamento generale sui servizi dell'istruzione
elementare), provides that the crucifix must form part of the “necessary
equipment and supplies in school classrooms”.
20. The Lateran Pacts, signed
on 11 February 1929, marked the “Conciliation” of the Italian State
and the Catholic Church. Catholicism was confirmed as Italy's
official religion, Article 1 of the Conciliation Treaty being worded as
follows:
“Italy recognizes and reaffirms the
principle established in the first Article of the Italian Constitution dated
March 4 1848, according to which the Roman Catholic Apostolic religion is the
only State religion.”
21. In 1948 Italy adopted its republican
Constitution, Article 7 of which provides: “The State and the Catholic Church, each
in its own order, shall be independent and sovereign ... their relations shall
be regulated by the Lateran Pacts [and] amendments to the Pacts accepted by
both parties shall not require proceedings to revise the Constitution.” Article
8 provides: “All religious creeds shall be equally free before the law ...
religious creeds other than Catholicism shall have the right to organise in
accordance with their own statutes, in so far as these are not incompatible
with the Italian legal order [and] their relations with the State shall be
determined by the law on the basis of agreements with their respective
representatives”.
22. The Protocol to the new
concordat, of 18 February 1984, ratified by Law no. 121 of 25 March 1985, states
that the principle laid down in the Lateran Pacts, that the Catholic religion
is the only State religion, is no longer in force.
23. In a judgment of 12 April
1989 (no. 203), rendered in a case which raised the question of the
non-compulsory nature of Catholic religious instruction in State schools, the
Constitutional Court held that the principle of secularism was derived from the
Constitution, ruling that it implied not that the State should be indifferent
to religions but that it should guarantee the protection of the freedom of
religion in a context of confessional and cultural pluralism.
Dealing in the present case with an
application concerning the conformity of the presence of crucifixes in State-school
classrooms with the principle of secularism, the Constitutional Court ruled
that it did not have jurisdiction, since the texts which required the presence
of the crucifix were only regulations (decision of 15 December 2004, no. 389; see
paragraph 14 above). When called upon to examine this question, the Consiglio di Stato held that, regard
being had to the meaning that should be attached to it, the presence of the
crucifix in State-school classrooms was compatible with the principle of
secularism (judgment of 13 February 2006, no. 556; see paragraph 16 above).
In a different case, the Court of Cassation had
taken the contrary view to that of the Consiglio
di Stato in the context of a prosecution for refusing to serve as a
scrutineer in a polling station on the ground that a crucifix was displayed
there. In its judgment of 1 March 2000 (no. 439), it held that the presence of
the crucifix infringed the principles of secularism and the impartiality of the
State, and the principle of the freedom of conscience of those who did not accept
any allegiance to that symbol. It expressly rejected the argument that
displaying the crucifix was justified in that it was the symbol of “an entire
civilisation or the collective ethical conscience” and – here the Court of
Cassation cited the terms used by the Consiglio di Stato in an
opinion of 27 April 1988 (no. 63) – also symbolised “a universal value
independent of any specific religious creed”.
24. On 3 October 2002 the
Minister of Education, Universities and Research issued the following
instruction (no. 2666):
“... The Minister
... Considering that the presence of crucifixes
in classrooms is founded on the provisions in force, that it offends neither
against religious pluralism nor against the objectives of multicultural
education of Italian schools and that it cannot be considered a limitation of
the freedom of conscience guaranteed by the Constitution, since it does not
refer to a specific creed but constitutes only an expression of Christian civilisation
and culture, and that it therefore forms part of the universal heritage of
mankind;
Having assessed, with respect for different
allegiances, convictions and beliefs, the desirability of requiring all schools,
within the limits of their own autonomy and by decision of their competent
collegiate organs, to set aside part of their premises to be used, without any
obligation and without any fixed hours being appointed, for contemplation and
meditation by those members of the school community who so wish;
Issues the following instruction:
The Ministry's competent service ... shall
take the necessary measures to see to it that:
1) school governors ensure the presence of
crucifixes in classrooms;
2) all schools, within the limits of their own
autonomy, and by decision of the members of their collegiate organs, set aside
part of their premises to be used, without any obligation and without any fixed
hours being appointed, for contemplation and meditation by
those members of the school community who so wish ...”.
25. Articles 19, 33 and 34 of
the Constitution are worded as follows:
Article 19
“Everyone is entitled to freely profess their
religious beliefs in any form, individually or with others, and to promote them
and celebrate rites in public or in private, provided that they are not
offensive to public morality.”
Article 33
“The Republic guarantees the freedom of the
arts and sciences, which may be freely taught.
The Republic lays down general rules for
education and establishes State schools of all branches and grades. ...”
Article 34
“Schools are open to everyone.
Elementary education, given for at least eight
years, is compulsory and free. ...”
III. OVERVIEW
OF LAW AND PRACTICE IN THE MEMBER STATES OF THE COUNCIL OF EUROPE WITH REGARD
TO THE PRESENCE OF RELIGIOUS SYMBOLS IN STATE SCHOOLS
26. In the great majority of
member States of the Council of Europe the question of the presence of
religious symbols in State schools is not governed by any specific regulations.
27. The presence of religious
symbols in State schools is expressly forbidden only in a small number of
member States: the former Yugoslav Republic of
Macedonia, France
(except in Alsace and the département of Moselle) and Georgia.
It is only expressly prescribed – in addition
to Italy – in a few member
States, namely: Austria,
certain administrative regions of Germany
(Länder) and Switzerland (communes),
and Poland.
Nevertheless, such symbols are found in the State schools of some member States
where the question is not specifically regulated, such as Spain, Greece,
Ireland, Malta, San Marino
and Romania.
28. The question has been
brought before the supreme courts of a number of member States.
In Switzerland the Federal Court has held a
communal ordinance prescribing the presence of crucifixes in primary school
classrooms to be incompatible with the requirements of confessional neutrality
enshrined in the Federal Constitution, but without criticising such a presence
in other parts of the school premises (26 September 1990; ATF 116 1a 252).
In Germany the Federal Constitutional Court has ruled
that a similar Bavarian ordinance was contrary to the principle of the State's
neutrality and difficult to reconcile with the freedom of religion of children
who were not Catholics (16 May 1995; BVerfGE 93,1). The Bavarian parliament
then issued a new ordinance maintaining the previous measure, but enabling
parents to cite their religious or secular convictions in challenging the
presence of crucifixes in the classrooms attended by their children and
introducing a mechanism whereby, if necessary, a compromise or a personalised
solution could be reached.
In Poland the Ombudsman referred to
the Constitutional Court
an ordinance of 14 April 1992 issued by the Minister of Education prescribing
in particular the possibility of displaying crucifixes in State-school
classrooms. The Constitutional Court ruled that the measure was compatible with
the freedom of conscience and religion and the principle of the separation of
Church and State guaranteed by Article 82 of the Constitution, given that it
did not make such display compulsory (20 April 1993; no. U 12/32).
In Romania the Supreme Court set aside a
decision of the National Council for the Prevention of Discrimination of 21
November 2006 recommending to the Ministry of Education that it should regulate
the question of the presence of religious symbols in publicly run educational
establishments and, in particular, authorise the display of such symbols only
during religious studies lessons or in rooms used for religious instruction.
The Supreme Court held in particular that the decision to display such symbols
in educational establishments should be a matter for the community formed by
teachers, pupils and pupils' parents (11 June 2008; no. 2393).
In Spain the High Court of Justice of Castile
and Leon, ruling in a case brought by an association militating in favour of
secular schooling which had unsuccessfully requested the removal of religious
symbols from schools, held that the schools concerned should remove them if
they received an explicit request from the parents of a pupil (14 December
2009; no. 3250).
THE LAW
I. ALLEGED VIOLATION OF ARTICLE 2
OF PROTOCOL No. 1 AND ARTICLE 9 OF THE CONVENTION
29. The applicants complained
of the fact that crucifixes were affixed to the wall in the classrooms of the
State school attended by the second and third applicants. They argued that this
infringed the right to education, guaranteed by Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 in
the following terms:
“No person shall be denied the right to
education. In the exercise of any functions which it assumes in relation to
education and to teaching, the State shall respect the right of parents to
ensure such education and teaching in conformity with their own religious and
philosophical convictions.”
They also contended that these facts infringed
their right to the freedom of thought, conscience and religion enshrined in
Article 9 of the Convention, which provides as follows:
“1. Everyone has the right to
freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to
change his religion or belief and freedom, either alone or in community with
others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief, in
worship, teaching, practice and observance.
2. Freedom to manifest one's
religion or beliefs shall be subject only to such limitations as are prescribed
by law and are necessary in a democratic society in the interests of public
safety, for the protection of public order, health or morals, or for the
protection of the rights and freedoms of others.”
A. The Chamber's judgment
30. In its judgment of 3 November
2009 the Chamber held that there had been a violation of Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1 taken together with Article 9 of the Convention.
31. First of all, the Chamber
derived from the principles relating to the interpretation of Article 2 of
Protocol No. 1 established in the Court's case-law an obligation on the State
to refrain from imposing beliefs, even indirectly, in places where persons were
dependent on it or in places where they were particularly vulnerable,
emphasising that the schooling of children was a particularly sensitive area in
that respect.
The Court went on to say that among the
plurality of meanings the crucifix might have the religious meaning was
predominant. It accordingly considered that the compulsory and highly visible
presence of crucifixes in classrooms was capable not only of clashing with the
secular convictions of the first applicant, whose children attended at that
time a State school, but also of being emotionally disturbing for pupils of
non-Christian religions or those who professed no religion. On that last point,
the Chamber emphasised that the “negative” freedom of religion was not limited
to the absence of religious services or religious education: it extended to practices
and symbols expressing, in particular or in general, a belief, a religion or
atheism. It added that this “negative right” deserved special protection if it was the State
which expressed a belief and dissenters were placed in a situation from which
they could not extract themselves if not by making disproportionate efforts and
sacrifices.
According to the Chamber, the State had a duty
to uphold confessional neutrality in public education, where school attendance
was compulsory regardless of religion, and which had to seek to inculcate in
pupils the habit of critical thought. It observed in addition that it could not
see how the display in State-school classrooms of a symbol that it was
reasonable to associate with the majority religion in Italy could serve the educational
pluralism which was essential for the preservation of “democratic society”
within the Convention meaning of that term.
32. The Chamber concluded
that “the compulsory display of a symbol of a particular faith in the exercise
of public authority in relation to specific situations subject to governmental
supervision, particularly in classrooms, restrict[ed] the right of parents to
educate their children in conformity with their convictions and the right of
schoolchildren to believe or not believe”. The practice infringed those rights
because “the restrictions [were] incompatible with the State's duty to respect
neutrality in the exercise of public authority, particularly in the field of
education” (§ 57 of the judgment).
B. Arguments of the parties
1. The Government
33. The Government did not raise
an objection of inadmissibility.
34. They regretted that the
Chamber had not had available to it a comparative law study of relations
between the State and religions and on the question of the display of religious
symbols in State schools. They asserted that the Chamber had thus deprived
itself of an essential element, since such a study would have shown that there
was no common approach in Europe in these fields, and would accordingly have
led it to the finding that the member States had a particularly wide margin of
appreciation; consequently, the Chamber, in its judgment, had failed to take that
margin of appreciation into consideration, thus ignoring one fundamental aspect
of the problem.
35. The Government also
criticised the Chamber's judgment for deriving from the concept of confessional
“neutrality” a principle excluding any relations between the State and a
particular religion, whereas neutrality required the public administrative
authorities to take all religions into account. The judgment was accordingly
based on confusion between “neutrality” (an “inclusive concept”) and
“secularism (an “exclusive concept”). Moreover, in the Government's view, neutrality
meant that States should refrain from promoting not only a particular religion
but also atheism, “secularism” on the State's part being no less problematic
than proselytising by the State. The Chamber's judgment was thus based on a
misunderstanding and amounted to favouring an irreligious or antireligious
approach of which the applicant, as a member of the Union
of atheists and rationalist agnostics, was asserted to be a militant supporter.
36. The Government went on to
argue that it was necessary to take account of the fact that a single symbol
could be interpreted differently from one person to another. That applied in
particular to the sign of the cross, which could be perceived not only as a
religious symbol, but also as a cultural and identity-linked symbol, the symbol
of the principles and values which formed the basis of democracy and western civilisation;
it appeared, for instance, on the flags of a number of European countries.
Whatever the evocative power of an “image” might be, in the Government's view,
it was a “passive symbol”, whose impact on individuals was not comparable with the
impact of “active conduct”, and no one had asserted in the present case that
the content of the teaching provided in Italy was influenced by the
presence of crucifixes in classrooms.
That presence was the expression of a
“national particularity”, characterised notably by close relations between the
State, the people and Catholicism attributable to the historical, cultural and territorial
development of Italy
and to a deeply rooted and long-standing attachment to the values of
Catholicism. Keeping crucifixes in schools was therefore a matter of preserving
a centuries-old tradition. The Government argued that the right of parents to
respect for their “family culture” ought not to infringe the community's right
to transmit its culture or the right of children to discover it. Moreover, by contenting
itself with a “potential risk” of emotional disturbance in finding a breach of
the rights to education and freedom of thought, conscience and religion, the
Chamber had considerably widened the scope of those provisions.
37. Referring in particular
to the Otto-Preminger-Institut v. Austria
judgment of 20 September 1994 (Series A no. 295-A), the Government contended
that, although account should be taken of the fact that the Catholic religion
was that of a large majority of Italians, this was not in order to make that fact
into an aggravating circumstance, as the Chamber had done. On the contrary, the
Court should acknowledge and protect national traditions and the prevailing
popular feeling, and leave each State to maintain a balance between opposing
interests. Moreover, it was the Court's case-law that school curricula or
provisions establishing the preponderance of the majority religion did not in
themselves point to undue influence on the part of the State or attempted
indoctrination, and that the Court should respect constitutional traditions and
principles relating to relations between the State and religions – including in
the present case the particular approach to secularism which prevailed in Italy
– and take into account the context of each State.
38. Considering
in addition that the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 was
applicable only to school curricula, the Government criticised the Chamber's
judgment for the finding of a violation without any indication of how the mere
presence of a crucifix in the classrooms where the first applicant's children
were taught was capable of substantially reducing her ability to bring them up in
conformity with her convictions, the only reason given being that pupils would
feel that they were being educated in a school environment marked by a
particular religion. That reason was erroneous when judged by the yardstick of
the Court's case-law, from which it could be seen in particular, firstly that
the Convention did not prevent member States from having a State religion, or
from showing a preference for a particular religion, or from providing pupils
with more extensive religious teaching in relation to the dominant religion,
and secondly that account had to be taken of the fact that the educational
influence of parents was much greater than the school's.
39. In
the Government's view, the presence of crucifixes in classrooms made a
legitimate contribution to enabling children to understand the national
community in which they were expected to integrate. An “environmental
influence” was all the more improbable because children in Italy received an education which
helped them to develop a critical outlook on the question of religion, in a
dispassionate atmosphere from which any form of proselytising was excluded.
Moreover, Italy had opted for a benevolent approach to minority religions in
the school environment: Italian law currently conferred the right to wear
Islamic headscarves and other apparel or symbols with a religious connotation;
the beginning and end of Ramadan were often celebrated in schools; religious
instruction was permitted for all recognised creeds; and the needs of pupils
belonging to minority faiths were taken into account, with Jewish pupils, for
example, being entitled not to sit examinations on Saturdays.
40. Lastly,
the Government emphasised the need to take into account the right of parents
who wanted crucifixes to be kept in classrooms. That was the wish of the
majority in Italy
and was also the wish democratically expressed in the present case by almost
all the members of the school's governing body. Removing crucifixes from
classrooms in such circumstances would amount to “abuse of a minority position”
and would be in contradiction with the State's duty to help individuals satisfy
their religious needs.
2. The applicants
41. The applicants submitted
that the display of crucifixes in the classrooms of the State school attended
by the second and third applicants constituted an illegitimate interference
with their right to the freedom of thought and conscience and infringed the
principle of educational pluralism in that it was the expression of the State's
preference for a particular religion in a place where conscience was formed. By
expressing that preference the State was also disregarding its obligation to
give special protection to minors against any form of propaganda or
indoctrination. Moreover, according to the applicants, since the educational
environment was thus marked by a symbol of the dominant religion, the display
of the crucifix which they complained of infringed the second and third
applicants' right to receive an open and pluralistic education aimed at the development
of a capacity for critical judgement. Lastly, as the first applicant was in
favour of secularism, it infringed her right to have her children educated in
conformity with her own philosophical convictions.
42. The applicants argued
that the crucifix was without a shadow of a doubt a religious symbol and trying
to attribute a cultural value to it savoured of an attempt to maintain a
hopeless last-ditch defence. Nor did anything in the Italian legal system justify
the assertion that it was a symbol of national identity: according to the Constitution,
it was the flag which symbolised that identity.
Moreover, as the German Federal Constitutional Court had
pointed out in its judgment of 16 May 1995 (see paragraph 28 above), giving the
crucifix a profane meaning would move it away from its original meaning and
help divest it of its sacred nature. As to the assertion that it was merely a
“passive symbol”, this ignored the fact that like all symbols – and more than
all others – it gave material form to a cognitive, intuitive and emotional reality
which went beyond the immediately perceptible. The German Federal Constitutional Court had,
moreover, made that finding, holding in the judgment cited above that the presence
of crucifixes in classrooms had an evocative character in that it represented
the content of the faith it symbolised and served as “publicity material” for
it. Lastly, the applicants pointed out that in the Dahlab v. Switzerland decision of 15 February 2001 (no. 42393/98, ECHR
2001-V), the Court had noted the particular power that religious symbols
exerted in the school environment.
43. The applicants contended
that every democratic State had a duty to guarantee the freedom of conscience,
pluralism, equal treatment of beliefs and the secular nature of institutions. The
principle of secularism required above all neutrality on the part of the State,
which should keep out of the religious sphere and adopt the same attitude with
regard to all religious currents. In other words, neutrality obliged the State
to establish a neutral space within which everyone could freely live according
to his own beliefs. By imposing religious symbols, namely crucifixes, in
classrooms, the Italian
State was doing the
opposite.
44. The approach advocated by
the applicants was thus clearly distinct from State atheism, which amounted to
denying the freedom of religion by imposing a secular viewpoint in an
authoritarian manner. Seen in terms of the State's impartiality and neutrality,
secularism was on the contrary a means of securing the religious and
philosophical freedom of conscience of all.
45. The applicants further
contended that it was essential to give special protection to minority beliefs
and convictions, in order to preserve those who held them from a “despotism of
the majority”, and that too was a reason for removing crucifixes from
classrooms.
46. In conclusion, the
applicants argued that although, as the Government maintained, removing
crucifixes from State-school classrooms would take away part of Italian
cultural identity, keeping them there was incompatible with the foundations of
western political thought, the principles of the liberal State and a pluralist,
open democracy, and respect for the individual rights and freedoms enshrined in
the Italian Constitution and the Convention.
C. Submissions of the third-party
interveners
1. The Governments of Armenia, Bulgaria,
Cyprus, the Russian Federation, Greece,
Lithuania, Malta and the Republic of San Marino
47. In their joint
observations submitted at the hearing, the Governments of Armenia, Bulgaria,
Cyprus, the Russian Federation, Greece, Lithuania, Malta and the Republic of
San Marino indicated that in their view the Chamber's reasoning had been based
on a misunderstanding of the concept of “neutrality”, which the Chamber had
confused with “secularism”. They pointed out that there was a huge diversity of
Church-State arrangements in Europe and that more than half the population of Europe lived in non-secular States. They added that State
symbols inevitably had a place in state education and that many of these had a
religious origin, the Cross – which was both a national and a religious symbol
– being the most visible example. In their view, in non-secular European States
the presence of religious symbols in the public space was widely tolerated by
the secular population as part of national identity. States should not have to
divest themselves of part of their cultural identity simply because that
identity was of religious origin. The position adopted by the Chamber was not
an expression of the pluralism manifest in the Convention system, but an
expression of the values of a secular State. To extend it to the whole of
Europe would represent the “Americanisation” of Europe
in that a single and unique rule and a rigid separation of Church and State
would be binding on everyone.
In their submission, favouring secularism was
a political position that, whilst respectable, was not neutral. Accordingly, in
the educational sphere a State that supported the secular as opposed to the
religious was not being neutral. Similarly, removing crucifixes from classrooms
where they had always been would not be devoid of educational consequences. In
reality, whether the State opted to allow or prohibit the presence of crucifixes
in classrooms, the important factor was the degree to which the curriculum
contextualised and taught children tolerance and pluralism.
The intervening Governments acknowledged that
there might be circumstances where the arrangements by the State were
unacceptable. The burden of proof should remain on the individual, however, and
the Court should intervene only in extreme cases.
2. The Government of the Principality
of Monaco
48. The intervening
Government declared that they shared the viewpoint of the respondent Government
according to which the crucifix was a “passive symbol” that was found on the coats
of arms and flags of many States and in the instant case reflected a national
identity rooted in history. Furthermore, being indivisible, the principle of
State neutrality required the authorities to refrain from imposing a religious
symbol where there had never been one and from withdrawing one that had always
been there.
3. The Government of Romania
49. The intervening
Government submitted that the Chamber had taken insufficient account of the
wide margin of appreciation available to the Contracting States where sensitive
issues were involved and that there was no European-wide consensus. They
pointed out that the Court's case-law recognised in particular that the States
enjoyed a wide margin of appreciation regarding the wearing of religious
symbols in State schools; in their submission, the same should apply to the
display of religious symbols in such schools. They also pointed out that the
Chamber judgment had been based on the premise that the display of religious
symbols in State schools breached Article 9 of the Convention and Article 2 of
Protocol No. 1, which conflicted with the principle of neutrality because,
where applicable, Contracting States were compelled to intervene with a view to
removing those symbols. In their view, that principle was better served where decisions
of this type were taken jointly by teachers, pupils and parents. In any event,
as it was not associated with particular religious obligations, the presence of
the crucifix in classrooms did not sufficiently affect the religious feelings
of those concerned for there to be a violation of the aforementioned
provisions.
4. The non-governmental organisation
Greek Helsinki
Monitor
50. According to the
intervening organisation, the crucifix could not be perceived as anything other
than a religious symbol, so that displaying it in State-school classrooms could
be seen as an institutional message advocating a particular religion. It
pointed out that in the case of Folgerø the Court had held that the participation of pupils in religious activities
could in fact influence them, and considered that the same was true where they
were taught in classrooms where a religious symbol was displayed. It also drew
the Court's attention to the fact that children or parents who were bothered by
this might refrain from protesting
for fear of reprisals.
5. The non-governmental organisation Associazione nazionale del libero Pensiero
51. The intervening
organisation, which considered that the presence of religious symbols in State-school
classrooms was incompatible with Article 9 of the Convention and Article 2 of
Protocol No. 1, submitted that the restrictions imposed on the applicants'
rights were not “prescribed by law” within the meaning of the Court's case-law.
It pointed out in that connection that displaying the crucifix in State-school
classrooms was prescribed not by law but by regulations adopted during the fascist
era. It added that those regulations had in any event been implicitly repealed
by the Constitution of 1947 and the Law of 1985 ratifying the agreements
amending the Lateran Pacts of 1929. It pointed out that the Criminal Division
of the Court of Cassation had ruled accordingly in a judgment of 1 March 2000
(no. 4273) in a similar case relating to crucifixes displayed in polling stations
and that it had confirmed that approach in a judgment of 17 February 2009
concerning crucifixes displayed in courtrooms (without, however, ruling on the
merits). There was therefore a conflict of case-law between the Consiglio di Stato – which, on the
contrary, held that the relevant regulations were applicable – and the Court of
Cassation that affected the principle of legal security, which was the pillar
of a State governed by the rule of law. As the Constitutional Court had declined
jurisdiction, there was no mechanism in Italy whereby this conflict could
be resolved.
6. The non-governmental organisation
European Centre for Law and Justice
52. The intervening
organisation submitted that the Chamber had wrongly addressed the question
raised by the case, which was whether the Convention rights invoked by the
first applicant had been violated merely on account of the presence of the
crucifix in classrooms. Its view was that they had not. Firstly, the “personal convictions”
of the first applicant's children had not been violated because they had neither
been compelled to act against their conscience nor prevented from acting
according to their conscience. Secondly, their “innermost convictions” and the
first applicant's right to ensure their education in conformity with her own
philosophical convictions had not been violated because her children had
neither been forced to believe nor prevented from not believing. They had not
been indoctrinated; nor had they been the subject of misplaced proselytism. The
intervening organisation submitted that the Chamber had been mistaken in
holding that a State's decision to display crucifixes in classrooms was
contrary to the Convention (which was not the question that had been submitted
to it). In doing so, the Chamber had created “a new obligation relating not to
the first applicant's rights, but to the nature of the “educational
environment”. In the intervening organisation's submission, it was because it
had been unable to establish that the first applicant's children's “innermost
or personal convictions” had been violated on account of the presence of the
crucifix in the classrooms that the Chamber had created a new obligation to
ensure that the educational environment was entirely secular, thus exceeding
the scope of the application and the limits of its jurisdiction.
7. The non-governmental organisation
Eurojuris
53. The intervening
organisation agreed with the Chamber's conclusions. After reiterating the
relevant provisions of Italian positive law – and underscoring the
constitutional value of the principle of secularism – it referred to the
principle established in the Court's case-law to the effect that school should
not be a place for proselytism or preaching. It also referred to cases in which
the Court had examined the question of the wearing of Islamic veils in
educational establishments. It went on to point out that the presence of
crucifixes in Italian State-school classrooms had been prescribed not by law
but by regulations inherited from the fascist era which reflected a confessional
conception of the State today that was incompatible with the principle of
secularism laid down in positive constitutional law. It firmly rejected the
reasoning of the Italian
Administrative Court, according to which
prescribing the presence of crucifixes in State-school classrooms was still
compatible with that principle because they symbolised secular values. In its
submission, it was a religious symbol with which non-Christians did not
identify. Moreover, by obliging schools to display it in State-school
classrooms the State conferred a particular dimension on a given religion, to
the detriment of pluralism.
8. The non-governmental organisations
International Commission of Jurists, Interights and Human Rights Watch
54. The intervening
organisations submitted that the compulsory display of religious symbols such
as the crucifix in State-school classrooms was incompatible with the principle
of neutrality and the rights guaranteed to pupils and their parents under Article
9 of the Convention and Article 2 of Protocol No. 1. In their submission,
educational pluralism was an established principle, upheld not only in the
Court's case-law but also in the case-law of a number of supreme courts and in
various international instruments. Furthermore, the Court's case-law supported
a duty of State neutrality and impartiality as among religious beliefs in the
provision of public services, including education. They pointed out that this
principle of impartiality was recognised not only by the Italian, Spanish and
German Constitutional Courts but also, in particular, by the French Conseil d'Etat and the Swiss Federal
Court. They added that, as several supreme courts had held, State neutrality as
among religious beliefs was particularly important in the classroom because,
school being compulsory, children were vulnerable to indoctrination at school. They
went on to reiterate the Court's finding that, although the Convention did not
prevent States from imparting through teaching or education information or
knowledge of a religious or philosophical kind, they had to ensure that this
was done in an objective, critical and pluralistic manner, and free of any indoctrination.
They stressed that the same applied to all functions carried out in the area of
education and teaching, including the organisation of the school environment.
9. The non-governmental organisations
Zentralkomitee der deutschen
katholiken, Semaines sociales de France and Associazioni cristiane lavoratori italiani
55. The intervening
organisations stated that they agreed with the Chamber that, whilst the
crucifix had a plural meaning, it was primarily the central symbol of Christianity.
They added, however, that they disagreed with its conclusion, and found it
difficult to understand how the presence of crucifixes in classrooms could be
“emotionally disturbing” for some pupils or hinder the development of their
critical thinking. In their submission, that presence alone could not be
equated with a religious or philosophical message; it should rather be
interpreted as a passive way of conveying basic moral values. The question
accordingly had to be regarded as one that fell within the competence of the
State when deciding on the curriculum in schools; parents had to accept that
certain aspects of State-school education could not be entirely in keeping with
their convictions. They added that a State's decision to display crucifixes in
State-school classrooms did not mean that it pursued an aim of indoctrination
prohibited by Article 2 of Protocol No. 1. They maintained that a balance had
to be found in the present case between the rights and interests of believers
and non-believers, between the fundamental rights of individuals and the
legitimate interests of society, and between the formulation of standards
relating to fundamental rights and maintaining the diversity existing in Europe. In their submission, the Court should leave a
wide margin of appreciation to the States in this area because the organisation
of the relationship between the State and religion varied from one country to
another and – in particular regarding the place of religion in State schools – was
deeply rooted in the history, tradition and culture of a country.
10. Thirty-three members of the
European Parliament acting collectively
56. The interveners pointed
out that the Court was not a constitutional court and had to respect the principle
of subsidiarity and recognise a particularly broad margin of appreciation in
favour of Contracting States not only regarding the relationship between the
State and religion but also where they carried out their functions in the area
of education and teaching. In their view, by taking a decision whose effect
would be to make it compulsory to remove religious symbols from State schools,
the Grand Chamber would be sending a radical ideological message. They added
that it was clear from the Court's case-law that a State which, for reasons deriving
from its history or its tradition, showed a preference for a particular
religion did not exceed that margin. Accordingly, in their opinion, the display
of crucifixes in public buildings did not conflict with the Convention, and the
presence of religious symbols in the public space should not be seen as a form
of indoctrination but the expression of a cultural unity and identity. They
added that in this specific context religious symbols had a secular dimension
and should therefore not be removed.
D. The Court's assessment
57. In the first place, the
Court observes that the only question before it concerns the compatibility, in
the light of the circumstances of the case, of the presence of crucifixes in
Italian State-school classrooms with the requirements of Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1 and Article 9 of the Convention.
Thus it is not required in this case to
examine the question of the presence of crucifixes in places other than State
schools. Nor is it for the Court to rule on the compatibility of the presence of
crucifixes in State-school classrooms with the principle of secularism as
enshrined in Italian law.
58. Secondly, the Court
emphasises that the supporters of secularism are able to lay claim to views
attaining the “level of cogency, seriousness, cohesion and importance” required
for them to be considered “convictions” within the meaning of Articles 9 of the
Convention and 2 of Protocol No. 1 (see Campbell
and Cosans v. the United Kingdom, 25 February 1982, § 36, Series A no. 48).
More precisely, their views must be regarded as “philosophical convictions”,
within the meaning of the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1, given
that they are worthy of “respect 'in a democratic society'”, are not incompatible
with human dignity and do not conflict with the fundamental right of the child
to education (ibid.).
1. The case of the first applicant
a. General principles
59. The Court reiterates that
in the area of education and teaching Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 is in
principle the lex specialis in
relation to Article 9 of the Convention. That is so at least where, as in the
present case, the dispute concerns the obligation laid on Contracting States by
the second sentence of Article 2 to respect, when exercising the functions they
assume in that area, the right of parents to ensure such education and teaching
in conformity with their own religious and philosophical convictions (see Folgerø and Others
v. Norway
[GC], no.
15472/02, § 84, ECHR 2007‑VIII, § 84).
The
complaint in question should therefore be examined mainly from the standpoint
of the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 (see also Appel-Irrgang and Others v. Germany (dec.), no. 45216/07, ECHR 2009‑...).
60. Nevertheless,
that provision should be read in the light not only of the first sentence of
the same Article, but also, in particular, of Article 9 of the Convention (see,
for example, Folgerø, cited above, § 84), which guarantees freedom of
thought, conscience and religion, including the freedom not to belong to a religion,
and which imposes on Contracting States a “duty of neutrality and impartiality”.
In that
connection, it should be pointed out that States have responsibility for ensuring, neutrally and impartially, the exercise of various religions, faiths
and beliefs. Their role is to help maintain public order, religious harmony and
tolerance in a democratic society, particularly between opposing groups (see, for
example, Leyla Şahin v. Turkey [GC], no. 44774/98, § 107, ECHR
2005‑XI). That concerns both relations between believers
and non-believers and relations between the adherents of various religions, faiths
and beliefs.
61. The word “respect” in
Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 means more than “acknowledge” or “take into account”;
in addition to a primarily negative undertaking, it implies some positive
obligation on the part of the State (see Campbell
and Cosans, cited above, § 37).
Nevertheless, the requirements of the notion
of “respect”, which appears also in Article 8 of the Convention, vary
considerably from case to case, given the diversity of the practices followed
and the situations obtaining in the Contracting States. As a result, the
Contracting States enjoy a wide margin of appreciation in determining the steps
to be taken to ensure compliance with the Convention with due regard to the
needs and resources of the community and of individuals. In the context of Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1 that concept implies in particular that this
provision cannot be interpreted to mean that parents can require the State to provide
a particular form of teaching (see Bulski
v. Poland (dec.), nos. 46254/99 and 31888/02).
62. The
Court would also refer to its case-law on the place of religion in the school curriculum
(see essentially Kjeldsen, Busk Madsen and Pedersen v. Denmark, 7 December 1976, §§ 50-53,
Series A no. 23; Folgerø, cited above, § 84; and Hasan and Eylem Zengin v. Turkey, no. 1448/04, §§ 51 and 52, ECHR 2007‑XI).
According to those authorities, the setting
and planning of the curriculum fall within the competence of the Contracting
States. In principle it is not for the Court to rule on such questions, as the
solutions may legitimately vary according to the country and the era.
In particular, the second sentence of Article
2 of Protocol No. 1 does not prevent States from imparting through teaching or
education information or knowledge of a directly or indirectly religious or
philosophical kind. It does not even permit parents to object to the
integration of such teaching or education in the school curriculum.
On the other hand, as its aim is to safeguard
the possibility of pluralism in education, it requires the State, in exercising
its functions with regard to education and teaching, to take care that
information or knowledge included in the curriculum is conveyed in an
objective, critical and pluralistic manner, enabling pupils to develop a
critical mind particularly with regard to religion in a calm atmosphere free of
any proselytism. The State is forbidden to pursue an aim of indoctrination that
might be considered as not respecting parents' religious and philosophical
convictions. That is the limit that the States must not exceed (see judgments
cited above in this paragraph, §§ 53, 84 (h) and 52 respectively).
b. Assessment of the facts of the
case in the light of the above principles
63. The Court does not accept
the Government's argument that the obligation laid on Contracting States by the
second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 concerns only the content
of school curricula, so that the question of the presence of crucifixes in State-school
classrooms would fall outside its scope.
It is true that a number of cases in which the
Court has examined this provision concerned the content and implementation of the
school curriculum. Nevertheless, as the Court has already emphasised, the obligation
on Contracting States to respect the religious and philosophical convictions of
parents does not apply only to the content of teaching and the way it is
provided; it binds them “in the exercise” of all the “functions” – in the terms
of the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 – which they assume in
relation to education and teaching (see essentially Kjeldsen, Busk Madsen and Pedersen, cited above, § 50; Valsamis v. Greece, 18 December 1996, § 27, Reports
of Judgments and Decisions 1996‑VI; Hasan and
Eylem Zengin, cited above, § 49; and Folgerø, cited
above, § 84). That
includes without any doubt the organisation of the school environment where
domestic law attributes that function to the public authorities.
It is in that context that the presence of
crucifixes in Italian State-school classrooms is to be placed (see Article
118 of royal decree no. 965 of 30 April 1924, Article 119 of royal decree
no. 1297 of 26 April 1928 and Articles 159 and 190 of legislative decree
no. 297 of 16 April 1994 – paragraphs 14 and 19 above).
64. In general, the Court
considers that where the organisation of the school environment is a matter for
the public authorities, that task must be seen as a function assumed by the
State in relation to education and teaching, within the meaning of the second
sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1.
65. It follows that the
decision whether crucifixes should be present in State-school classrooms forms
part of the functions assumed by the respondent State in relation to education
and teaching and, accordingly, falls within the scope of the second sentence of
Article 2 of Protocol No. 1. That makes it an area in which the State's
obligation to respect the right of parents to ensure the education and teaching
of their children in conformity with their own religious and philosophical
convictions comes into play.
66. The Court further considers
that the crucifix is above all a religious symbol. The domestic courts came to
the same conclusion and in any event the Government have not contested this. The
question whether the crucifix is charged with any other meaning beyond its
religious symbolism is not decisive at this stage of the Court's reasoning.
There is no evidence before the Court that the
display of a religious symbol on classroom walls may have an influence on
pupils and so it cannot reasonably be asserted that it does or does not have an
effect on young persons whose convictions are still in the process of being
formed.
However, it is understandable that the first
applicant might see in the display of crucifixes in the classrooms of the State
school formerly attended by her children a lack of respect on the State's part
for her right to ensure their education and teaching in conformity with her own
philosophical convictions. Be that as it may, the applicant's subjective perception
is not in itself sufficient to establish a breach of Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1.
67. The Government, for their
part, explained that the presence of crucifixes in State-school classrooms,
being the result of Italy's
historical development, a fact which gave it not only a religious connotation
but also an identity-linked one, now corresponded to a tradition which they
considered it important to perpetuate. They added that, beyond its religious
meaning, the crucifix symbolised the principles and values which formed the
foundation of democracy and western civilisation, and that its presence in
classrooms was justifiable on that account.
68. The Court takes the view
that the decision whether or not to perpetuate a tradition falls in principle within
the margin of appreciation of the respondent State. The Court must moreover take
into account the fact that Europe is marked by
a great diversity between the States of which it is composed, particularly in
the sphere of cultural and historical development. It emphasises, however, that
the reference to a tradition cannot relieve a Contracting State
of its obligation to respect the rights and freedoms enshrined in the
Convention and its Protocols.
As regards the Government's opinion on the
meaning of the crucifix, the Court notes that the Consiglio di Stato and the Court of Cassation have diverging views
in that regard and that the Constitutional
Court has not given a ruling (see paragraphs 16
and 23 above). It is not for the Court to take a position regarding a domestic
debate among domestic courts.
69. The fact remains that the
Contracting States enjoy a margin of appreciation in their efforts to reconcile
exercise of the functions they assume in relation to education and teaching with
respect for the right of parents to ensure such education and teaching in
conformity with their own religious and philosophical convictions (see
paragraphs 61-62 above).
That applies to organisation of the school
environment and to the setting and planning of the curriculum (as the Court has
already pointed out: see essentially the judgments cited above in the cases of Kjeldsen, Busk Madsen and Pedersen, §§
50-53; Folgerø, § 84; and Zengin, §§ 51-52; paragraph 62 above).
The Court therefore has a duty in principle to respect the Contracting States'
decisions in these matters, including the place they accord to religion,
provided that those decisions do not lead to a form of indoctrination (ibid.).
70. The Court concludes in
the present case that the decision whether crucifixes
should be present in State-school classrooms is, in principle, a matter
falling within the margin of appreciation of the respondent State. Moreover, the
fact that there is no European consensus on the question of the presence of
religious symbols in State schools (see paragraphs 26-28 above) speaks in
favour of that approach.
This margin of appreciation, however, goes
hand in hand with European supervision (see, for example, mutatis mutandis, Leyla Şahin,
cited above, § 110), the Court's task in the present case being to
determine whether the limit mentioned in paragraph 69 above has been exceeded.
71. In that connection, it is
true that by prescribing the presence of crucifixes in State-school classrooms
– a sign which, whether or not it is accorded in addition a secular symbolic
value, undoubtedly refers to Christianity – the regulations confer on the country's
majority religion preponderant visibility in the school environment.
That is not in itself sufficient, however, to denote
a process of indoctrination on the respondent State's part and establish a breach
of the requirements of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1.
The Court refers on this point, mutatis mutandis, to the previously
cited Folgerø and Zengin judgments. In the Folgerø case, in which it was called
upon to examine the content of “Christianity, religion and philosophy” (KRL)
lessons, it found that the fact that the syllabus gave a larger share to
knowledge of the Christian religion than to that of other religions and
philosophies could not in itself be viewed as a departure from the principles
of pluralism and objectivity amounting to indoctrination. It explained that in
view of the place occupied by Christianity in the history and tradition of the
respondent State – Norway – this question had to be regarded as falling within
the margin of appreciation left to it in planning and setting the curriculum (see
Folgerø, cited above, § 89). It
reached a similar conclusion in the context of “religious culture and ethics”
classes in Turkish schools, where the syllabus gave greater prominence to
knowledge of Islam on the ground that, notwithstanding the State's secular
nature, Islam was the majority religion practised in Turkey (see Zengin, cited above, § 63).
72. Furthermore, a crucifix
on a wall is an essentially passive symbol and this point is of importance in
the Court's view, particularly having regard to the principle of neutrality (see
paragraph 60 above). It cannot be deemed to have an influence on pupils
comparable to that of didactic speech or participation in religious activities
(see on these points Folgerø and Zengin, cited above, § 94 and § 64
respectively).
73. The Court observes that,
in its judgment of 3 November 2009, the Chamber agreed with the submission that
the display of crucifixes in classrooms would have a significant impact on the
second and third applicants, aged eleven and thirteen at the time. The Chamber
found that, in the context of public education, crucifixes, which it was
impossible not to notice in classrooms, were necessarily perceived as an
integral part of the school environment and could therefore be considered “powerful
external symbols” within the meaning of the decision in Dahlab, cited above (see §§ 54 and 55 of the judgment).
The Grand Chamber does not agree with that approach. It considers that that decision cannot serve as a basis in this
case because the facts of the two cases are entirely different.
It points out that the case of Dahlab concerned the measure prohibiting
the applicant from wearing the Islamic headscarf while teaching, which was
intended to protect the religious beliefs of the pupils and their parents and
to apply the principle of denominational neutrality in schools enshrined in
domestic law. After observing that the authorities had duly weighed
the competing interests involved, the Court held, having regard above all to
the tender age of the children for whom the applicant was responsible, that the
authorities had not exceeded their margin of appreciation.
74. Moreover, the effects of
the greater visibility which the presence of the crucifix gives to Christianity
in schools needs to be further placed in perspective by consideration of the
following points. Firstly, the presence of crucifixes is not associated with compulsory
teaching about Christianity (see the comparative-law information set out in Zengin, cited above, § 33). Secondly,
according to the indications provided by the Government, Italy opens up the school
environment in parallel to other religions. The Government indicated in this
connection that it was not forbidden for pupils to wear Islamic headscarves or
other symbols or apparel having a religious connotation; alternative arrangements
were possible to help schooling fit in with non-majority religious practices; the
beginning and end of Ramadan were “often celebrated” in schools; and optional
religious education could be organised in schools for “all recognised religious
creeds” (see paragraph 39 above). Moreover, there was nothing to suggest that
the authorities were intolerant of pupils who believed in other religions, were
non-believers or who held non-religious philosophical convictions.
In addition, the applicants did not assert
that the presence of the crucifix in classrooms had encouraged the development
of teaching practices with a proselytising tendency, or claim that the second
and third applicants had ever experienced a tendentious reference to that
presence by a teacher in the exercise of his or her functions.
75. Lastly, the Court notes
that the first applicant retained in full her right as a parent to enlighten
and advise her children, to exercise in their regard her natural functions as educator
and to guide them on a path in line with her own philosophical convictions (see,
in particular, Kjeldsen, Busk Madsen and
Pedersen and Valsamis, cited
above, §§ 54 and 31 respectively).
76. It follows from the
foregoing that, in deciding to keep crucifixes in the classrooms of the State
school attended by the first applicant's children, the authorities acted within
the limits of the margin of appreciation left to the respondent State in the
context of its obligation to respect, in the exercise of the functions it
assumes in relation to education and teaching, the right of parents to ensure
such education and teaching in conformity with their own religious and
philosophical convictions.
77. The Court accordingly
concludes that there has been no violation of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 in
respect of the first applicant. It further considers that no separate issue
arises under Article 9 of the Convention.
2. The case of the second and third
applicants
78. The Court considers that,
when read as it should be in the light of Article 9 of the Convention and the
second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1, the first sentence of that
provision guarantees schoolchildren the right to education in a form which
respects their right to believe or not to believe. It therefore understands why
pupils who are in favour of secularism may see in the presence of crucifixes in
the classrooms of the State school they attend an infringement of the rights
they derive from those provisions.
However, it considers, for the reasons given
in connection with its examination of the first applicant's case, that there
has been no violation of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 in respect of the second
and third applicants. It further considers that no separate issue arises in the
case under Article 9 of the Convention.
II. ALLEGED VIOLATION OF ARTICLE
14 OF THE CONVENTION
79. The applicants submitted
that because the second and third applicants had been exposed to the crucifixes
displayed in the classrooms of the State school they attended, all three of
them, not being Catholics, had suffered a discriminatory difference in
treatment in relation to Catholic parents and their children. Arguing that “the
principles enshrined in Article 9 of the Convention and Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1 are reinforced by the provisions of Article 14 de la Convention”, they
complained of a violation of the latter Article, which provides:
“The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set
forth in [the] Convention shall be secured without discrimination on any ground
such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion,
national or social origin, association with a national minority, property,
birth or other status.”
80. The Chamber held that,
regard being had to the circumstances of the case and the reasoning which had
led it to find a violation of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 taken together with
Article 9 of the Convention, there was no cause to examine the case under
Article 14 also, whether taken separately or in conjunction with those
provisions.
81. The Court, which notes
that little argument has been presented in support of this complaint, reiterates
that Article 14 of the Convention has no independent existence, since it has
effect solely in relation to the enjoyment of the rights and freedoms
safeguarded by the other substantive provisions of the Convention and its
Protocols.
Proceeding on the assumption that the
applicants wished to complain of discrimination regarding their enjoyment of
the rights guaranteed by Article 9 of the Convention and Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1 on account of the fact that they were not adherents of the Catholic
religion and that the second and third of them had been exposed to the sight of
crucifixes in the classrooms of the State school they attended, the Court does
not see in those complaints any issue distinct from those it has already
determined under Article 2 of Protocol No. 1. There is accordingly no cause to
examine this part of the application.
FOR THESE
REASONS, THE COURT
1. Holds, by fifteen votes to two, that there has been no violation of
Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 and that no separate issue arises under
Article 9 of the Convention;
2. Holds unanimously that there is no cause to examine the complaint
under Article 14 of the Convention.
Done in English and in French, and
delivered at a public hearing in the Human Rights Building, Strasbourg, on 18 March 2011.
Erik Fribergh Jean-Paul
Costa
Registrar President
Registrar President
In accordance with Article 45 § 2 of the
Convention and Rule 74 § 2 of the Rules of Court, the following separate
opinions are annexed to this judgment:
(a) Concurring opinion of Judge Rozakis
joined by Judge Vajić;
(b) Concurring opinion of Judge Bonello;
(c) Concurring opinion of Judge
Power;
(d) Dissenting opinion of Judge
Malinverni joined by Judge Kalaydjieva.
J.-P.C.
E.F.
E.F.
CONCURRING OPINION OF JUDGE ROZAKIS JOINED
BY JUDGE VAJIĆ
BY JUDGE VAJIĆ
The main issue to be resolved in this case is
the effect of the application of the proportionality test to the facts.
Proportionality between, on the one hand, the right of parents to ensure their
children's education and teaching in conformity with their own religious and
philosophical convictions, and, on the other hand, the right or interest of at
least a very large segment of society to display religious symbols as a
manifestation of religion or belief. Consequently, both the competing values
involved in this case are simultaneously protected by the Convention, through
Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 (the lex
specialis), read in the light of Article 9 of the Convention, in so far as
the parents are concerned, and Article 9 of the Convention, in so far as
society's rights are concerned.
Concerning, first, the parents' right, the
Court's judgment underlines that the word “respect” in the second sentence of
Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 “means more than 'acknowledge' or 'take into
account'; in addition to a primarily negative obligation, it implies some
positive obligation on the part of the State” (see paragraph 61 of the
judgment). Yet the respect due to the parents, even in the form of some
positive obligation, “does not prevent States from imparting through teaching
or education information or knowledge of a directly or indirectly religious or
philosophical kind. It does not even permit parents to object to the
integration of such teaching or education in the school curriculum” (see
paragraph 62).
This last reference to the Convention's case-law
needs, I think, some further analysis. It is indisputable that Article 2 of
Protocol No. 1 enshrines the fundamental right to education: a sacrosanct
individual right – which undoubtedly can also be seen from the angle of a
social right – that seems to be constantly gaining ground in our European
societies. However, while the right to education constitutes one of the
cornerstones of the protection of individuals under the Convention, the same
cannot be said with equal force, to my mind, of the subordinate right of
parents to ensure their children's education in accordance with their religious
or philosophical beliefs. Here matters differ considerably, for a number of
reasons:
(i) that right, although linked to
the right to education, does not directly vest in the basic recipient of the
right, namely, in the recipient of the education, that is, the one who has the
right to be educated. It vests in the parents – whose direct right to education
is not at stake in the circumstances – and is limited to one aspect of
education alone: their religious and philosophical convictions.
(ii) although there is admittedly
an obvious relationship between the education that children receive in their
schools and the religious and philosophical ideas and opinions, deriving from
convictions, which exist in the family environment – a relationship that
requires a degree of harmonisation in these matters between the school and home
environments – Europe has nevertheless changed dramatically regarding this
aspect as well as others since Protocol No. 1 was adopted. Most of us now live
in multicultural, multi-ethnic societies within our national States, a feature
which has become a common characteristic of those societies, and children
living in that environment are exposed, in their everyday life, to ideas and
opinions which go beyond those emanating from school and their parents. Human
relations outside the parental roof and modern means of communication
undoubtedly contribute to that effect. As a consequence, children become
accustomed to receiving a variety of frequently conflicting ideas and opinions
and the role of both school and parents in these matters has become relatively
less influential.
(iii) as a result of the changed
composition of our societies, it is increasingly difficult for a State to cater
for the individual needs of parents on educational issues. I would go as far as
saying that its main concern, and this is a valid concern, should be to offer
children an education which will ensure their fullest integration into the
society in which they live and prepare them, in the best possible way, to cope
effectively with the expectations that that society has of its members.
Although this characteristic of education is not a new one – it has
existed since time immemorial – it has recently acquired more obvious
importance because of the particularities of our era and the composition of
societies today. Again, the duties of the State have largely shifted from
concerns of parents to concerns of society at large, thus reducing the extent
of the parents' ability to determine, outside the home, the kind of education
that their children receive.
In conclusion, it seems to me that, unlike
other guarantees of the Convention, in respect of which the case-law of the
Convention has increased the purview of protection, including the right to
education, the right of parents, under the second sentence of Article 2 of
Protocol No. 1, does not seem realistically to be gaining weight in the
balancing exercise of the proportionality test.
At the other end of the spectrum,
representing the other limb of the proportionality equation, lies the right of
society, as reflected in the authorities' measure in maintaining crucifixes on
the walls of State schools, to manifest their (majority) religious beliefs.
Does this right, in the circumstances of the case, override the right of
parents to educate their children in accordance with their religion and
– more specifically in the circumstances of the present case – their
philosophical convictions?
The answer should be given by interpreting
the Convention case-law and applying it to the particular circumstances of this
case. And the first question which must be settled is the issue of a European
consensus. Is there any European consensus on the matter – allowing,
imposing or prohibiting the display of Christian religious symbols in State
schools – which should determine the position of the Court on the matter?
The answer emerges clearly from this very
judgment of the Court, and from the part dealing with the overview of law and
practice in the member States of the Council of Europe with regard to the
presence of religious symbols in “State schools” (see paragraphs 26 et seq.):
there is no consensus among European States prohibiting the presence of such religious
symbols, and few States expressly forbid them. There is, of course, a growing
trend towards proscribing the possibility of displaying crucifixes in State
schools – mainly through rulings of the higher national courts – but
the number of States that have adopted measures prohibiting the display of
crucifixes in public places and the extent of domestic judicial activity do not
allow the Court to presume that a consensus has been reached against displaying
them. This is particularly true if one takes into account that there are a
number of States in Europe where the Christian religion is still the official
or predominant religion and, moreover, as I have just underscored, that a
number of States clearly allow, through their law or practice, crucifixes to be
displayed in public places.
It should be observed here, while we are on
the subject of a consensus, that the Court is a court of law, not a legislative
body. Whenever it embarks on a search for the limits of the Convention's
protection, it carefully takes into consideration the existing degree of
protection at the level of the European States; it can, of course, afford to
develop that protection at a level higher than the one offered by a specific
respondent State, but on condition that there are strong indications that a
great number of other European States have already adopted that degree of
protection, or that there is a clear trend towards an increased level of
protection. That principle cannot positively apply in the present case,
although there is admittedly an emerging trend towards prohibiting the display
of religious symbols in public institutions.
In view of the fact that there is still a
mixed practice among European States on the issue, the only remaining guidance
for the Court in achieving the correct balance between the rights involved
comes from its prior case-law. The keywords deriving from the prior case-law
are “neutrality and impartiality”. As the Court has noted in the present
judgment, “States have responsibility for ensuring, neutrally and impartially,
the exercise of various religions, faiths and beliefs. Their role is to help
maintain public order, religious harmony and tolerance in a democratic society,
particularly between opposing groups” (see paragraph 60, in fine).
It is, I think, indisputable that the display
of crucifixes in Italian State schools has a religious symbolism that has an
impact on the obligation of neutrality and impartiality of the State, despite
the fact that in a modern European society symbols seem to be gradually losing
the very important weight that they used to have in the past and more pragmatic
and rationalistic approaches now determine, for large segments of the
population, the real social and ideological values.
The question which therefore arises at this
juncture is whether the display of the crucifix not only affects neutrality and
impartiality, which it clearly does, but whether the extent of the
transgression justifies a finding of a violation of the Convention in the
circumstances of the present case. Here I conclude, not without some
hesitation, that it does not, in accordance with the main reasoning of the
Court's approach and, more particularly, the role of the majority religion of
Italian society (see paragraph 71), the essentially passive nature of the
symbol, which cannot amount to indoctrination (see paragraph 72), and also the
educational context within which the crucifix appears on the walls of State
schools. As the judgment has pointed out, “[f]irstly, the presence of
crucifixes is not associated with compulsory teaching about Christianity ...
Secondly ... Italy
opens up the school environment in parallel to other religions. The Government
indicated in this connection that it was not forbidden for pupils to wear
Islamic headscarves or other symbols or apparel having a religious connotation;
alternative arrangements were possible to help schooling fit in with
non-majority religious practices; ... and optional religious education could be
organised in schools for 'all recognised religious creeds'...” (see
paragraph 74 of the judgment). These elements, demonstrating a religious
tolerance which is expressed through a liberal approach allowing all religions
denominations to freely manifest their religious convictions in State schools,
are, to my mind, a major factor in “neutralising” the symbolic importance of
the presence of the crucifix in State schools.
I would also say that this same liberal
approach serves the very concept of “neutrality”; it is the other side of the
coin from, for example, a policy of prohibiting any religious symbols from
being displayed in public places.
CONCURRING
OPINION OF JUDGE BONELLO
1.1 A court of human rights cannot
allow itself to suffer from historical Alzheimer's. It has no right to
disregard the cultural continuum of a nation's flow through time, nor to ignore
what, over the centuries, has served to mould and define the profile of a
people. No supranational court has any business substituting its own ethical
mock-ups for those qualities that history has imprinted on the national
identity. On a human rights court falls the function of protecting fundamental
rights, but never ignoring that “customs are not passing whims. They evolve
over time, harden over history into cultural cement. They become defining, all-important
badges of identity for nations, tribes, religions, individuals”.[1]
1.2 A European court should not be
called upon to bankrupt centuries of European tradition. No court, certainly
not this Court, should rob the Italians of part of their cultural personality.
1.3 I believe that before joining
any crusade to demonise the crucifix, we should start by placing the presence
of that emblem in Italian schools in its rightful historical perspective. For
many centuries, virtually the only education in Italy was provided by the Church,
its religious orders and organisations – and very few besides. Many, if not
most schools, colleges, universities and other institutes of learning in Italy
had been founded, funded, or run by the Church, its members or its offshoots.
The milestones of history turned education and Christianity into almost
interchangeable notions, and because of this, the age-old presence of the
crucifix in Italian schools should come as no shock or surprise. In fact, its
absence would have come as a surprise and a shock.
1.4 Until relatively recently, the
“secular” State had hardly bothered with education, and, by default, had
delegated that primary function to Christian institutions. Only slowly did the
State start assuming its responsibilities to educate and to offer the
population some alternatives to a virtual religious monopoly on education. The
presence of the crucifix in Italian schools only testifies to this compelling
and millennial historical reality – it could loosely be said that it has been
there since schools have been there. Now, a court in a glass box a thousand
kilometres away has been engaged to veto overnight what has survived countless
generations. The Court has been asked to be an accomplice in a major act of
cultural vandalism. I believe William Faulkner went to the core of the issue:
the past is never dead. In fact it is not even past.[2]
Like it or not, the perfumes and the stench of history will always be with you.
1.5 It is uninformed nonsense to
assert that the presence of the crucifix in Italian schools bears witness to a
reactionary fascist measure imposed, in between gulps of castor oil, by Signor Mussolini. His circulars merely
took formal notice of a historical reality that had predated him by several
centuries and, pace Ms Lautsi's
anti-crucifix vitriol, may still survive him for a long time. This Court ought
to be ever cautious in taking liberties with other peoples' liberties,
including the liberty of cherishing their own cultural imprinting. Whatever
that is, it is unrepeatable. Nations do not fashion their histories on the spur
of the moment.
1.6 The scansion of the Italian
school calendar further testifies to
the inextricable historical links between education and religion in Italy,
obstinate ties which have lasted throughout the centuries. School children to
the very present day toil on the days consecrated to the pagan gods
(Diana/Luna, Mars, Hercules, Jove, Venus, Saturn) and rest on Sunday (domenica, the day of the Lord). The
school calendar apes the religious calendar closely – holidays double the
Christian ones: Easter, Christmas, Lent, Carnival (carnevale, the time when church discipline allowed the consumption
of meat), the Epiphany, Pentecost, the Assumption, Corpus Domini, Advent, All
Saints, All Souls: an annual cycle far more glaringly non-secularist than any
crucifix on any wall. May it please Ms Lautsi, in her own name and on behalf of
secularism, not to enlist the services of this Court to ensure the suppression
of the Italian school calendar, another Christian-cultural heritage that has
survived the centuries without any evidence of irreparable harm to the progress
of freedom, emancipation, democracy and civilisation.
What
rights? Freedom of religion and conscience?
2.1 The issues in this controversy
have been fudged by a deplorable lack of clarity and definition. The Convention
enshrines the protection of freedom of religion and of conscience (Article 9).
Nothing less, obviously, but little more.
2.2 In parallel with freedom of
religion, there has evolved in civilised societies a catalogue of noteworthy
(often laudable) values cognate to, but different from, freedom of religion,
like secularism, pluralism, the separation of Church and State, religious
neutrality, religious tolerance. All of these represent superior democratic
commodities which Contracting States are free to invest in or not to invest in,
and many have done just that. But these
are not values protected by the Convention, and it is fundamentally flawed
to juggle these dissimilar concepts as if they were interchangeable with
freedom of religion. Sadly, traces of such all but rigorous overspill appear in
the Court's case-law too.
2.3 The Convention has given this
Court the remit to enforce freedom of religion and of conscience, but has not
empowered it to bully States into secularism or to coerce countries into
schemes of religious neutrality. It is for each individual State to choose
whether to be secular or not, and whether, and to what extent, to separate
Church and governance. What is not for the State to do is to deny freedom of
religion and of conscience to anyone. An immense, axiomatic chasm separates one
prescriptive concept from the other non-prescriptive ones.
2.4 Most of the arguments raised
by the applicant called upon the Court to ensure the separation of Church and
State and to enforce a regime of aseptic secularism in Italian schools.
Bluntly, that ought to be none of this Court's business. This Court has to see
that Ms Lautsi and her children enjoy to the full their fundamental right
to freedom of religion and conscience. Period.
2.5 The Convention proves to be
quite helpful with its detailed and exhaustive inventory of what freedom of
religion and conscience really means, and we would do well to keep these
institutional constraints in mind. Freedom of religion is not secularism. Freedom of religion is not the separation of Church and State. Freedom of religion is not religious equidistance – all
seductive notions, but of which no one has so far appointed this Court to be
the custodian. In Europe, secularism is
optional, freedom of religion is not.
2.6 Freedom of religion, and
freedom from religion, in substance, consist in the rights to profess freely
any religion of the individual's choice, the right to freely change one's
religion, the right not to embrace any religion at all, and the right to
manifest one's religion by means of belief, worship, teaching and observance.
Here the Convention catalogue grinds to a halt, well short of the promotion of
any State secularism.
2.7 This Court's rather modest
function remains that of determining whether the exposure in State schoolrooms
of what to some is a Christian symbol and to others a cultural gadget in any
way interfered with Ms Lautsi's and her children's basic right to freedom
of religion – as defined by the Convention itself.
2.8 I believe anyone could
persuasively try to argue that the presence of the crucifix in Italian State schools might possibly offend the
doctrine of secularism and that of the separation between Church and State. At
the same time I do not believe that anyone can persuasively plead that the
presence of a crucifix interfered in any way with the Lautsis' right to profess
any religion of their choice, to change their religion, not to have any religion
at all or to manifest their beliefs, if any, by worship, teaching and
observance, or with their right to reject outright anything they may consider
insipid superstitious junk.
2.9 With or without a crucifix on
a schoolroom wall, the Lautsis enjoyed the most absolute and untrammelled
freedom of conscience and religion as demarcated by the Convention. The
presence of a crucifix in a State classroom might conceivably be viewed as a
betrayal of secularism and an unjustifiable failure of the regime of separation
between Church and State – but these doctrines, however alluring and beguiling,
are nowhere mandated by the Convention, nor are they necessary constitutive
elements of the freedoms of conscience and of religion. It is for the Italian
authorities, not for this Court, to enforce secularism if they believe it forms
part, or should form part, of the Italian constitutional architecture.
2.10 Seen in the light of the
historical roots of the presence of the crucifix in Italian schools, removing
it from where it has quietly and passively been for centuries, would hardly
have been a manifestation of neutrality by the State. Its removal would have
been a positive and aggressive espousal of agnosticism or of secularism – and
consequently anything but neutral. Keeping a symbol where it has always been is
no act of intolerance by believers or cultural traditionalists. Dislodging it
would be an act of intolerance by agnostics and secularists.
2.11 Millions of Italian children
have, over the centuries, been exposed to the crucifix in schools. This has
neither turned Italy
into a confessional State, nor the Italians into citizens of a theocracy. The
applicants have failed to unfurl before the Court any evidence at all that
those exposed to the crucifix forfeited in any way their complete freedom to
manifest their individual and personal religious belief, or their right to
repudiate any religion. The presence of a crucifix in a schoolroom does not
seem to have hindered any Italian in his or her liberty to believe or to
disbelieve, to embrace atheism, agnosticism, anti-clericalism, secularism,
materialism, relativism, or doctrinaire irreligion, to recant, apostatise, or
to embrace whatever creed or “heresy” of their choice they find sufficiently
appealing, with the same vigour and gusto others freely embrace a Christian
faith. Had any such evidence been adduced, I would have been strident in my
voting for finding a violation of the Convention.
What
rights? Right to education?
3.1 Article 2 of Protocol No. 1
guarantees the right of parents to ensure that the teaching their children receive is in conformity with their own
religious and philosophical convictions. The Court has to supervise and ensure
respect for this right.
3.2 Does the mere silent and
passive presence of a symbol in a classroom in an Italian school amount to
“teaching”? Does it hinder the exercise of the guaranteed right? Try hard as I
might, I fail to see how. The Convention specifically and exclusively bans any teaching in schools unwelcome to parents
on religious, ethical and philosophical grounds. The keyword of this norm is
obviously “teaching” and I doubt how far the mute presence of a symbol of
European cultural continuity would amount to teaching in any sense of that
fairly unambiguous word.
3.3 In my view, what the
Convention prohibits are any indoctrination, arrant or devious, the aggressive
confiscation of young minds, invasive proselytism, the putting in place by the
public educational system of any obstacle to the avowal of atheism, agnosticism
or alternative religious options. The mere display of a voiceless testimonial
of a historical symbol, so emphatically part of the European heritage, in no
way amounts to “teaching”, nor does it undermine in any meaningful manner the
fundamental right of parents to determine what, if any, religious orientation
their children are to follow.
3.4. But, even assuming that the
mere existence of a mute object should be construed as “teaching”, the
applicants have failed to answer the far more cardinal question of
proportionality, intimately related to the exercise of fundamental rights when
these conflict with the rights of others – the weighting to be given to the
various competing interests.
3.5 All the parents of all the
thirty pupils in an Italian classroom enjoy equally the fundamental Convention
right to have their children receive teaching in conformity with their own
religious and philosophical convictions, at least analogous to that of the
Lautsi children. The parents of one pupil want that to be “non-crucifix”
schooling, and the parents of the other twenty-nine, exercising their equally
fundamental freedom of decision, want that schooling to be “crucifix”
schooling. No one has so far suggested any reason why the will of the parents
of one pupil should prevail, and that of the parents of the other twenty-nine
pupils should founder. The parents of the twenty-nine have the fundamental
right, equivalent in force and commensurate in intensity, to have their
children receive teaching in conformity with their own religious and
philosophical convictions, be they crucifix-friendly or merely
crucifix-indifferent. Ms Lautsi cannot award herself a licence to overrule
the right of all the other parents of all the other pupils in that classroom,
who want to exercise the same right she has asked this Court to inhibit others
from exercising.
3.6 The crucifix purge promoted by
Ms Lautsi would not in any way be a measure to ensure neutrality in the
classroom. It would be an imposition of the crucifix-hostile philosophy of the
parents of one pupil, over the crucifix-receptive philosophy of the parents of
all the other twenty-nine. If the parents of one pupil claim the right to have
their child raised in the absence of a crucifix, the parents of the other
twenty-nine should well be able to claim an equal right to its presence,
whether as a traditional Christian emblem or even solely as a cultural
souvenir.
An
aside
4.1 Very recently, this Court was
called upon to determine whether a ban ordered by the Turkish authorities on
the distribution of Guillaume Apollinaire's novel Les onze mille verges could be justified in a democratic society.
That novel would only fail to qualify as fierce pornography through the most
lavish disregard of contemporary standards of morality.[3]
Yet the Court manfully saved that smear of transcendental smut on the ground
that it formed part of European cultural heritage.[4]
4.2 It would have been quite
bizarre, in my view, for this Court to protect and redeem an under-the-counter,
over-the-borderline discharge of nauseous obscenity on the ground of its
distinctly faint “European heritage” merit, and, in the same breath, deny
European heritage value to an emblem recognised over the centuries by millions
of Europeans as a timeless symbol of redemption through universal love.
CONCURRING
OPINION OF JUDGE POWER
This case raises issues as to the scope of
certain provisions of the Convention and the Grand Chamber's rectification of a
number of errors in the Chamber's Judgment was both necessary and appropriate.
The core correction consists in the finding that the decision as to whether
crucifixes should be present in state-school classrooms is, in principle, a
matter falling within the margin of appreciation of a respondent state (§ 70).
In exercising its supervisory role, the Court has confirmed its earlier case
law[5]
to the effect that the 'preponderant visibility' within a school environment
which a state may confer on a country's majority religion is not, in itself,
sufficient to indicate a process of indoctrination such as would establish a
breach of the requirements of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 (§ 71).
The Grand Chamber has also corrected the rather
speculative conclusion in the Chamber judgment (see § 55) as to the
“particularly strong” risk of emotional disturbance which the presence of a
crucifix may pose to children of minority religions or none. Given the critical
role of “evidence” in any Court proceedings, the Grand Chamber has correctly noted
that there was no evidence opened to the Court to indicate any influence which
the presence of a religious symbol may have on school pupils (§ 66). While acknowledging
as “understandable” the first applicant's perception of a lack of respect for
her rights, the Grand Chamber has confirmed that her subjective perception is
not sufficient to establish a breach of Article 2 of Protocol No 1. The first
applicant may have taken offence at the presence of a crucifix in classrooms but
the existence of a right 'not to be offended' has never been recognised within
the Convention. In reversing the Chamber's judgment, the Grand Chamber does no
more than confirm a body of settled jurisprudence (notably under Article 10)
which recognises that mere 'offence' is not something against which an
individual may be immunized by law.
However, there was another fundamental and,
in my view, erroneous conclusion in the Chamber's Judgment upon which the Grand
Chamber did not comment and which, to my mind, merited clarification. The
Chamber referred, correctly, to the State's duty to uphold confessional
neutrality in public education (§ 56). However, it proceeded, to conclude,
incorrectly, that this duty required the effective preference or elevation of
one ideology (or body of ideas) over all other religious and/or philosophical
perspectives or world views. Neutrality requires a pluralist approach on the
part of the State, not a secularist one. It encourages respect for all world
views rather than a preference for one. To my mind, the Chamber Judgment was
striking in its failure to recognise that secularism (which was the applicant's
preferred belief or world view) was, in itself, one ideology among others. A
preference for secularism over alternative world views—whether religious,
philosophical or otherwise—is not a neutral option. The Convention requires
that respect be given to the first applicant's convictions insofar as the
education and teaching of her children was concerned. It does not require a
preferential option for and endorsement of those
convictions over and above all others.
In his separate opinion, Judge Bonello has
pointed to the fact that within the European tradition, education (and, to my
mind, the values of human dignity, tolerance and respect for the individual,
without which there can be no lasting basis for human rights protection) is
rooted, historically, inter alia, within the Christian tradition. To prohibit
in public schools, regardless of the wishes of the body politic, the display of
a symbol representative of that (or indeed any other religious) tradition and
to require of the State that it pursues not a pluralist but a secularist
agenda, risks venturing towards the territory of intolerance – a concept that
is contrary to the values of the Convention.
The applicants complain of an alleged
violation of their rights to freedom of thought, conscience and religion. I can
find no interference with their freedom to manifest their personal beliefs. The
test of a violation under Article 9 is not “offence” but “coercion”.[6]
That article does not create a right not to be offended by the manifestation of
the religious beliefs of others even where those beliefs are given 'preponderant
visibility' by the State. The display of a religious symbol does not compel or
coerce an individual to do or to refrain from doing anything. It does not
require engagement in any activity though it may, conceivably, invite or
stimulate discussion and an open exchange of views. It does not prevent an
individual from following his or her own conscience nor does it make it
unfeasible for such a person to manifest his or her own religious beliefs and
ideas.
The Grand Chamber has found that the presence
of the crucifix is, essentially, a passive symbol and it regards this point as
being of great importance having regard to the principle of neutrality. I agree
with the Court in this regard insofar as the symbol's passivity is not in any
way coercive. However, I would have to concede that, in principle, symbols
(whether religious, cultural or otherwise) are carriers of meaning. They may be
silent but they may, nevertheless, speak volumes without, however, doing so in
a coercive or in an indoctrinating manner. The uncontested evidence before the
Court is that Italy
opens up the school environment to a variety of religions and there is no
evidence of any intolerance shown towards non-believers or those who hold
non-religious philosophical convictions. Islamic headscarves may be worn. The
beginning and end of Ramadan are “often celebrated”. Within such a pluralist
and religiously tolerant context, a Christian symbol on a classroom wall
presents yet another and a different world view. The presentation of and
engagement with different points of view is an intrinsic part of the educative
process. It acts as a stimulus to dialogue. A truly pluralist education involves
exposure to a variety of different ideas including those which are different
from one's own. Dialogue becomes possible and, perhaps, is at its most
meaningful where there is a genuine difference of opinion and an honest
exchange of views. When pursued in a spirit of openness, curiosity, tolerance
and respect, this encounter may lead towards greater clarity and vision as it
fosters the development of critical thinking. Education would be diminished if
children were not exposed to different perspectives on life and, in being so
exposed, provided with the opportunity to learn the importance of respect for
diversity.
DISSENTING OPINION OF JUDGE MALINVERNI
JOINED BY JUDGE KALAYDJIEVA
(Translation)
1. The
Grand Chamber has reached the conclusion that there has not been a violation of
Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 on the ground that “the decision whether
crucifixes should be present in State-school classrooms is, in principle, a
matter falling within the margin of appreciation of the respondent State” (see
paragraph 70, and also paragraph 69).
I have difficulty following that line of
argument. Whilst the doctrine of the margin of appreciation may be useful, or
indeed convenient, it is a tool that needs to be handled with care because the
scope of that margin will depend on a great many factors: the right in issue, the
seriousness of the infringement, the existence of a European consensus, etc. The
Court has thus affirmed that “the scope of this margin of appreciation is not
identical in each case but will vary according to the context ... . Relevant
factors include the nature of the Convention right in issue, its importance for
the individual and the nature of the activities concerned”.[7]
The proper application of this theory will thus depend on the importance to be
attached to each of these various factors. Where the Court decrees that the
margin of appreciation is a narrow one, it will generally find a violation of
the Convention; where it considers that the margin of appreciation is wide, the
respondent State will usually be “acquitted”.
In the present case it is by relying mainly
on the lack of any European consensus that the Grand Chamber has allowed itself
to invoke the doctrine of the margin of appreciation (see paragraph 70). In
that connection I would observe that, besides Italy, it is in only a very
limited number of member States of the Council of Europe (Austria, Poland,
certain regions of Germany (Länder) –
see paragraph 27) that there is express provision for the presence of religious
symbols in State schools. In the vast majority of the member States the
question is not specifically regulated. On that basis I find it difficult, in such
circumstances, to draw definite conclusions regarding a European consensus.
With regard to the regulations governing this
question, I would point out in passing that the presence of crucifixes in Italian State schools has an extremely weak
basis in law: a very old royal decree dating back to 1860, then a fascist
circular of 1922, and then royal decrees of 1924 and 1928. These are therefore
very old instruments, which, as they were not enacted by Parliament, are lacking
in any democratic legitimacy.
What I find more important, however, is that
where they have been required to give a ruling on the issue, the European supreme
or constitutional courts have always, without exception, given precedence to the
principle of State denominational neutrality: the German Constitutional Court,
the Swiss Federal Court, the Polish Constitutional Court and, in a slightly
different context, the Italian Court of Cassation (see paragraphs 28 and 23).
Be that as it may, one thing is certain: the
doctrine of the margin of appreciation should not in any circumstances exempt
the Court from the duty to exercise the function conferred on it under Article
19 of the Convention, which is to ensure the observance of the engagements
undertaken by the High Contracting Parties in the Convention and the Protocols
thereto. Now, the wording of the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1
confers a positive obligation on
States to respect the right of parents to ensure education and teaching in
conformity with their own religious and philosophical convictions.
That positive obligation derives from the
verb “respect”, which appears in Article 2 of Protocol No. 1. As the Grand
Chamber has rightly pointed out, “in addition to a primarily negative
undertaking, this verb implies some positive obligation on the part of the
State (see paragraph 61). Such a positive obligation can, moreover, also be
inferred from Article 9 of the Convention. That provision can be interpreted as
conferring on States a positive obligation to create a climate of tolerance and mutual respect among
their population.
Can it be maintained that the States properly
comply with that positive obligation where they mainly have regard to the
beliefs held by the majority? Moreover, is the scope of the margin of
appreciation the same where the national authorities are required to comply
with a positive obligation and where
they merely have to comply with an obligation of abstention? I do not
think so. I incline, rather, to the view that where the States are bound by positive
obligations their margin of appreciation is reduced.
In any event, according to the case-law, the
margin of appreciation is subject to European supervision. The Court's task then
consists in ensuring that the limit on the margin of appreciation has not been
overstepped. In the present case, whilst acknowledging that by prescribing the
presence of crucifixes in State-school classrooms the regulations confer on the
country's majority religion preponderant visibility in the school environment, the
Grand Chamber has taken the view that “that is not in itself sufficient,
however, to ... establish a breach of the requirements of Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1”. I cannot share that view.
2. We now
live in a multicultural society, in which the effective protection of religious
freedom and of the right to education requires strict State neutrality in State-school education,
which must make every effort to promote pluralism in education as a fundamental
feature of a democratic society within the meaning of the Convention.[8]
The principle of State neutrality has, moreover, been expressly recognised by
the Italian Constitutional Court
itself, in whose view it flows from the fundamental principle of equality of
all citizens and the prohibition of any discrimination that the State must
adopt an attitude of impartiality towards religious beliefs.[9]
The second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol
No. 1 implies that the State, in fulfilling the functions assumed by it in
regard to education and teaching, must take care that knowledge is conveyed in
an objective, critical and pluralistic manner. Schools should be a meeting
place for different religions and philosophical convictions, in which pupils
can acquire knowledge about their respective thoughts and traditions.
3. These
principles are valid not only for the devising and planning of the school curriculum, which are not in
issue in the present case, but also for the school
environment. Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 specifies that in the exercise of any functions which it assumes in
relation to education and to teaching the State shall respect the right of
parents to ensure such education and teaching in conformity with their own
religious and philosophical convictions. In other words, the principle of State
denominational neutrality applies not only to the content of the curriculum, but the
whole educational system. In the case of Folgerø the Court rightly pointed out that the duty conferred on the States
under that provision “is broad in its extent as it applies not only to the content of education and the manner of
its provision but also to the performance of all the 'functions' assumed by the State”.[10]
This view is shared by other both domestic
and international bodies. Thus, in its General Comment No.1, the United Nations
Committee on the Rights of the Child has affirmed that the right to education
refers “not only to the content of the curriculum, but also the educational
processes, the pedagogical methods and the environment
within which education takes place, whether it be the home, school, or
elsewhere”[11], and
also that “the school environment itself must
thus reflect the freedom and the spirit of understanding, peace, tolerance,
equality of sexes, and friendship among all peoples, ethnic, national and
religious groups”.[12]
The Supreme Court of Canada has also observed
that the school environment is an integral part of discrimination-free
education: “In order to ensure a discrimination-free educational environment, the school environment must be one where all are treated equally and
all are encouraged to fully participate.”[13]
4. Religious symbols are indisputably
part of the school environment. As such, they might therefore infringe the duty
of State neutrality and have an impact on religious freedom and the right to education.
This is particularly true where the religious symbol is imposed on pupils, even
against their will. As the German Constitutional Court observed in its famous
judgment: “Certainly, in a society that allows room for differing religious
convictions, the individual has no right to be spared from other manifestations
of faith, acts of worship or religious symbols. This is however to be distinguished
from a situation created by the State where the individual is exposed without
possibility of escape to the influence of a particular faith, to the acts
through which it is manifested and to the symbols in which it is presented”[14].
That view is shared by other supreme or constitutional courts.
Thus, the Swiss Federal Court has found that
the duty of denominational neutrality incumbent on the State is of special
importance in State schools, where schooling is compulsory. It went on to say
that, as guarantor of the denominational neutrality of the school system, the
State could not, where teaching was concerned, manifest its own attachment to a
particular religion, be it a majority or a minority one, because certain people
may feel that their religious beliefs are impinged upon by the constant presence
at school of the symbol of a religion to which they do not belong.[15]
5. The crucifix is undeniably a religious
symbol. The respondent Government argued that, in the context of the school
environment, the crucifix symbolised the religious origin of values that had
now become secular, such as tolerance and mutual respect. It thus fulfilled a
highly educational symbolic function, irrespective of the religion professed by
the pupils, because it was the expression of an entire civilisation and
universal values.
In my view, the presence of the crucifix in
classrooms goes well beyond the use of symbols in particular historical contexts.
The Court has moreover held that the traditional nature, in the social and historical
sense, of a text used by members of parliament when swearing loyalty did not
deprive the oath to be sworn of its religious nature.[16]
As observed by the Chamber, negative freedom of religion is not restricted to
the absence of religious services or religious education. It also extends to
symbols expressing a belief or a religion. That negative right deserves special
protection if it is the State which displays a religious symbol and dissenters
are placed in a situation from which they cannot extract themselves.[17]
Even if it is accepted that the crucifix can have multiple meanings, the
religious meaning still remains the predominant one. In the context of state
education it is necessarily perceived as an integral part of the school
environment and may even be considered as a powerful external symbol. I note,
moreover, that even the Italian Court of Cassation rejected the argument that
the crucifix symbolised values independent of a particular religious belief (see
paragraph 67).
6. The
presence of crucifixes in schools is capable of infringing religious freedom
and schoolchildren's right to education to a greater degree than religious
apparel that, for example, a teacher might wear, such as the Islamic headscarf.
In the latter example the teacher in question may invoke her own freedom of
religion, which must also be taken into account, and which the State must also
respect. The public authorities cannot, however, invoke such a right. From the
point of view of the seriousness of the infringement of the principle of State
denominational neutrality, this will accordingly be of a lesser degree where
the public authorities tolerate the headscarf in schools than where they impose
the presence of crucifixes.
7. The
impact which the presence of crucifixes may have in schools is also
incommensurable with the impact that they may have in other public establishments,
such as a voting booth or a court. As the Chamber rightly pointed out, in
schools “the compelling power of the State is imposed on minds which still lack
the critical capacity which would enable them to keep their distance from the
message derived from a preference manifested by the State” (see § 48 of the
Chamber judgment).
8. To
conclude, effective protection of the rights guaranteed by Article 2 of
Protocol No. 1 and Article 9 of the Convention requires States to observe the
strictest denominational neutrality. This is not limited to the school curriculum,
but also extends to “the school environment”. As primary and secondary
schooling are compulsory, the State should not impose on pupils, against their
will and without their being able to extract themselves, the symbol of a religion
with which they do not identify. In doing so, the respondent Government have
violated Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 and Article 9 of the Convention.
[1]. Justin Marozzi, The
Man who Invented History, John Murray, 2009, p. 97.
[2] Requiem for a nun,
1951.
[3]. Wikipedia classifies this work as “a pornographic
novel” in which the author “explores all aspects of sexuality: sadism
alternates with masochism; ondinism/scatophilia with vampirism; paedophilia
with genrontophilia; masturbation with group sex; lesbianism with homosexuality
... the novel exudes an infernal joy”.
[4]. Akdaş v. Turkey,
no. 41056/04, 16 February 2010.
[6]. See Buscarini and
Others v. San Marino [GC], no. 24645/94, ECHR 1999‑I; see also the Supreme Holy Council of the Muslim Community v.
Bulgaria, no. 39023/97, 16 December 2004.
[7]. Buckley v. the United Kingdom, 25 September
1996, § 74, Reports of Judgments and
Decisions 1996‑IV.
[8]. Manoussakis and
Others v. Greece, 26
September 1996, § 47; Kokkinakis v. Greece,
25 May 1993, § 31.
[9]. Italian
Constitutional Court, judgment no. 508/2000.
[10]. Folgerø and
Others v. Norway, 29 June 2007, § 84. Our italics.
[11]. Committee on the Rights of the Child, General Comment
No. 1, of 4 April 2001, “The Aims of Education”, para. 8. Our italics.
[12]. Idem, para.
19. Our italics.
[13]. Supreme Court of Canada, Ross v. New Brunswick School District no. 15, para. 100.
[14]. German
Constitutional Court, BVerfGE 93, I I BvR 1097/91,
judgment of 16 May 1995, § C (II) (1), non-official translation.
[15]. Swiss Federal Court, ATF 116 Ia 252, Comune di Cadro, judgment of 26 September 1990,
§ 7.
[16]. Buscarini and
Others v. San Marino [GC], no. 24645/94, ECHR 1999‑I.
[17]. Lautsi v. Italy,
no. 30814/06, § 55, 3 November 2009.
Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:
Δημοσίευση σχολίου